I myself believe, though my Stoic
comrades would be unwilling to hear me say so, that the teaching of Epicurus
was upright and holy, and even, if you examine it narrowly, strong: for this
much talked of pleasure is reduced to a very narrow compass, and he bids
pleasure submit to the same law which we bid virtue do—I mean, to obey Nature.
Luxury, however, is not satisfied with
what is enough for nature. What is the consequence? Whoever thinks that
happiness consists in lazy sloth, and alternations of gluttony and profligacy,
requires a good patron for a bad action, and when he has become an Epicurean,
having been led to do so by the attractive name of that school, he follows, not
the pleasure which he there hears spoken of, but that which he brought there
with him, and, having learned to think that his vices coincide with the maxims
of that philosophy, he indulges in them no longer timidly and in dark corners,
but boldly in the face of day.
I will not, therefore, like most of our
school, say that the sect of Epicurus is the teacher of crime, but what I say
is: it is ill spoken of, it has a bad reputation, and yet it does not deserve
it. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 13 (tr Stewart)
I have
never had much patience for any philosophy that is dogmatic and exclusive, since
the truth should be acquired through reasoning, not by authority, and it should
be something shared, not something fractured. This should apply especially to
Stoicism, ordered as it is toward the harmony of all things, and not toward
conflict.
I
learned to deeply respect the philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas precisely
because he was a thinker who was always willing and able to see the different
senses of meaning, and would always strive to point out what was common before
he explained a disagreement. I was always saddened by the sort of Thomists who
completely missed this point.
A
respect for others means that we can begin with what is shared, and then use
our own errors as a means to improvement. Seneca knows that there will be some
Stoics, perhaps more interested in the name than the task, who prefer to
condemn instead of understand. Seneca, however, is willing to give credit where
credit is due.
Epicurus
did indeed hold pleasure to be the highest good, but his conviction was that
such pleasure must always be calm and moderate, and should obey Nature. If this
is indeed the case, Seneca argues that passion must therefore actually follow reason and virtue, because any
pleasure is qualified and conditioned by whether it is understood to be good or
bad. Epicurus may have gotten the order of priority wrong in his thinking, but
he modeled a very similar way of living in his practice.
This, of
course, isn’t true of many of his followers, then and now, who would have
reason and virtue as slaves to unbridled desire. To be fair, such a
misunderstanding might be similar to that of an extreme Stoic who thinks that
virtue is just toughness, or that possessions are evil, or that pleasure should
be repressed.
I have
always hoped to discover something bigger than myself in a philosophy, and not
just impose my own preferences upon it.
Written in 8/2011
Image: Marble Bust of Epicurus (3rd c. BC)
No comments:
Post a Comment