Reflections on Seneca:
The Happy Life
Liam Milburn
Seneca
the Younger’s work, On the happy life,
has long been a great comfort and encouragement to me when times have been
hard, or when I have strayed from the right path. Writing to his brother Gallio, he reminds us
how the search for genuine happiness must be the measure by which we judge all
other things. He uses the truths of the Stoic tradition, as well as the
fullness of all Ancient wisdom, to help the reader consider what we must do to
live well, and how to avoid living poorly.
Over
more than two decades, I would choose a passage from one of the Stoic
philosophers in the early morning, read through it with great care, and usually
write down my own thoughts and experiences on the topic at hand. These were
never really intended for publication, but rather helped me to manage my own
day with as much serenity and dignity as I could muster.
In the
end, many of the passages and comments were joined together in A Stoic breviary: Classical wisdom in daily
practice, in the hope that a handful of others might also benefit from the
original philosophers. The Stoic
Reflections series, based upon certain themes, were something of a further
supplement.
I
eventually found that, quite by accident, I had over time written a full
commentary, often quite a few different times, on the complete texts of
Epictetus’ Handbook, Marcus Aurelius’
Meditations, and Seneca the Younger’s
On the happy life. Since these three
texts have always been at the heart of my own Stoic adventures, I offer them
separately for your consideration as well.
1. Where
to go, and how to get there?
All men, brother Gallio, wish to live
happily, but are dull at perceiving exactly what it is that makes life happy:
and so far is it from being easy to attain the happiness that the more eagerly
a man struggles to reach it the further he departs from it, if he takes the
wrong road; for, since this leads in the opposite direction, his very swiftness
carries him all the further away.
We must therefore first define clearly
what it is at which we aim: next we must consider by what path we may most
speedily reach it, for on our journey itself, provided it be made in the right
direction, we shall learn how much progress we have made each day, and how much
nearer we are to the goal towards which our natural desires urge us.
But as long as we wander at random, not
following any guide except the shouts and discordant clamors of those who
invite us to proceed in different directions, our short life will be wasted in
useless roamings, even if we labor both day and night to get a good
understanding. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 1 (tr Stewart)
Nothing
could be more important, yet nothing can seem so confusing. Everything depends
upon it, so we will try anything to achieve it. It is so clear that I desire it
above all else, and sometimes so obscure as to what it might be. I need to know
where I wish to go, and how I should get there, and this reveals why philosophy
is hardly just a luxury, but an absolute necessity.
We all
know that happiness is the highest good we aim for, even as we might offer
radically different accounts of its nature. I have found that we are often
tempted to only provide what we think are a list of synonyms, each just another
label that does not truly define what it means to be happy. Joy, contentment,
peace of mind, well-being, bliss, success, security, being fulfilled, pleasure,
enlightenment, purpose, meaning, ecstasy, salvation.
Note, however, that each of these terms can
have a different association, and can lead us down very different paths. If,
for example, I consider happiness a function of pleasure, or if I consider
happiness to be a function of wisdom, these will lead to quite distinct ways of
living.
In a
time when various forms of skepticism, subjectivism, and relativism are the
fashion of the moment, when we insist that we can really never know anything
for certain, that truth depends on my own beliefs, and that nothing is
therefore really true or false in itself, it is tempting to give the answer
that happiness is just different for everyone.
This
sounds terribly deep, but is actually a desperate cop-out. It is telling me
that something is defined by being nothing at all, and instead of isolating
what is common to all instances of something, it separates all the ways the
instances are dissimilar. We may well have many different definitions of
happiness, but this does not tell me which of them is true. We may all
experience happiness in ways particular to our own personality and
circumstances, but this does not tell me what is universally shared by all
these experiences.
I don’t,
however, usually see people grappling with the different senses of what
happiness could be at all, and instead I suggest that so many of us just ignore
the question altogether. We know we want this most wonderful of things, but we
are simply uncertain how to proceed in figuring out what it is, or how to
pursue it. Perhaps we sometimes do this out of dismissive arrogance, but I
think we do it just as often out of fear. I have often found myself not only
afraid of an effort, but also terrified of what I may learn about myself if I
were to follow through with that effort.
As soon
as I perceive that some things seem to make me happy, I am also admitting that
there are opposite things that will make me miserable. If I am wandering around
blindly and without direction, with no sense of what I am doing or why I am
doing it, all my choices and actions are in vain. Without a measure of meaning
and a sense of purpose, my life will quite literally be directionless.
I have
been lost in the woods, and I have been lost in the big city. I have even been
lost in a single building. It took me a whole year to figure out how to
navigate the rabbit warren of my high school. I have even felt lost in time
looking at a schedule, where the question wasn’t just where I should be, but
when I should be there. In each case, it was only finding a way to position
myself that got me out the mess. Where was I now, where did I need to be going,
and what was the best route to get there?
It will
hardly make any difference if I just tell myself I need to try harder, if I
don’t even know the right way to do something. Exerting more effort going in
the wrong direction will only get me further from where I need to be than if I
stood around feeling confused.
I have
sometimes gotten out of being lost with my own wits, by using a compass, or
looking at the sun, or making a mental image of my steps, or just finding a map
with that comforting “you are here” dot. At other times I have swallowed my
pride and asked for help. This isn’t as simple as it sounds, because ten different
people may give me ten different answers. Which answer is the best one? Do I
listen to the majority opinion, or do I consider which source seems to be the
best informed? How can I tell?
I
learned fairly quickly, not through the theory of the classroom, but through
the obstacles of daily life, that I would need to find that essential but
elusive purpose, and discover a way to point me in the right direction.
2. The
beaten path
. . . Let us not therefore decide
whether we must tend, and by what path, without the advice of some experienced
person who has explored the region which we are about to enter, because this
journey is not subject to the same conditions as others; for in some the distinctly
understood track and inquiries made of the natives make it impossible for us to
go wrong, but here the most beaten and frequented tracks are those which lead
us most astray.
Nothing, therefore, is more important
than that we should not, like sheep, follow the flock that has gone before us,
and thus proceed not where we ought, but where the rest are going. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy Life,
Chapter 1 (tr Stewart)
When in
Rome, they say, do as the Romans do. It is an almost immediate instinct for us
to conform to the socially approved standard. I think this has less to do with
our own conscious judgment than it does with a basic instinct to just be
accepted.
This is quite
reasonable when it comes to matters of custom and culture. I once deeply
offended an Indian host by eating with wrong hand, and at another time I was
criticized by a Russian for not finishing my entire glass of vodka. I adapted
fairly quickly, though the second experience was quite painful on the next day.
There
are beaten paths for many things. It is only reasonable to learn skills by
example, and to travel with the flow. I cannot count the number of practices
I’ve learned just by watching other people do them first. Observing a maniacal
friend playing the mandolin, at a lightning speed I thought would set the
instrument on fire, was far more helpful than all those instructional books or
chord charts, and it was only the fine model of my own teachers, over many
years, that ever made me an even barely competent teacher. We usually become
better by being the best of mimics.
Seneca
suggests that this is not so true when it comes to the path toward happiness.
What we see around us might not be so exemplary, and what others do might not
provide the best guidance. These are no longer matters of custom and culture,
but matters of right and wrong.
I
suspect the many will often be led astray because the most visible and outspoken
folks will lure us down a false path. The herd then follows. Consider how often
you have thought of a charming and respected person as a role model, and then
asked yourself if that was the best move you could have made. Allure and
position do not make the man.
Unlike
custom and culture, where we may humbly show our respect by following, the act
of living in happiness, and of living well, requires our own independent
thinking, and the act of our own deliberate choice. No one can ever do this job
for us, or command us to do it, because we have to take that first completely
autonomous step: we are our own masters, and responsible for ourselves. We must
each make that first plunge entirely on our own.
I
distinctly recall being ensnared, time and time again, by the appearance of
character, and being convinced that someone or something was worth following,
simply because so many other people were standing in line to get approval.
I was
once entranced by a professor who told me all about how academics was a
dedication to service, but then he suddenly left for a far better paying job,
abandoning all of his graduate students in mid-stream.
I was
once convinced that a very popular parish priest could do no harm, and I was
deeply moved by his appeals to marital fidelity, until I found he’d been
sleeping with women in his parish.
Human
nature can be a fickle thing, and we get it wrong more often than we get it
right. That professor was just a man, and that priest was just a man, and I
cannot claim to be any better. What surprised me about myself was how easily I
fell for an image, and for the popularity that came with it. I wasn’t judging
for myself, but I was letting other people do the judging for me.
Whatever
is popular gives me an easy excuse, to shut of my own conscience and depend
upon another. I think there is a real difference between someone who serves,
because he knows what he does, and someone who merely follows, because he is
led by the nose.
The
beaten path, the one all of the self-important people draw attention to, should
immediately be suspect. This is not out of any elitism, but out of the
recognition that weakness loves company. Users and abusers know that we are
struggling, so they will give us easy answers to difficult problems. They are
selling us a product, and they think that we will buy it because we are
uncertain and afraid.
The
problem with following the herd in matters of ethics isn’t about dismissing the
opinions of others. It’s all about choosing not to think for ourselves.
Submitting without judgment will be our doom. Embracing liberty with a sincere
conscience will be our redemption.
The
right teacher, the right role model, will never tell you what you must do. He
will point you toward what you must decide for yourself. You will recognize him
right away, because he is not selling you anything. He gives you himself, and
asks only that you humbly and sincerely be yourself.
3. The
lemmings were pushed
. . . Now nothing gets us into greater
troubles than our subservience to common rumor, and our habit of thinking that
those things are best which are most generally received as such, of taking many
counterfeits for truly good things, and of living not by reason but by
imitation of others.
This is the cause of those great heaps
into which men rush till they are piled one upon another. In a great crush of
people, when the crowd presses upon itself, no one can fall without drawing
someone else down upon him, and those who go before cause the destruction of
those who follow them.
You may observe the same thing in human
life: no one can merely go wrong by himself, but he must become both the cause
and adviser of another's wrong doing. It is harmful to follow the march of
those who go before us, and since everyone had rather believe another than form
his own opinion, we never pass a deliberate judgment upon life, but some
traditional error always entangles us and brings us to ruin, and we perish
because we follow other men's examples: we should be cured of this if we were
to disengage ourselves from the herd; but as it is, the mob is ready to fight
against reason in defense of its own mistake.
Consequently the same thing happens as
at elections, where, when the fickle breeze of popular favor has veered round,
those who have been chosen consuls and praetors are viewed with admiration by
the very men who made them so. That we should all approve and disapprove of the
same things is the end of every decision that is given according to the voice
of the majority.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 1 (tr Stewart)
Seneca’s
distrust of popular opinion may seem disturbing in our supposedly democratic
age, but I have never seen his argument as being based upon any inherent
superiority or inferiority of the few or the many. Rather, it rests upon a very
concrete observation about the individual choices that each one of us makes,
and why it is so much easier to conform than it is to think for oneself. The
draw of comfort and security can be strong, and it sometimes seems that doing
nothing, and blending in with the crowd, is safer and easier than doing
something, and risking exclusion.
Now the
inaction of avoiding a judgment will most often be far more dangerous than the
action of making a judgment, but it may certainly not seem so at the time. The
Stoic, of course, is quite aware of the danger of following impressions, and
not reflecting upon their meaning, and the Stoic is also attuned to the power
impressions have over us when we turn off our thinking.
What
some people call “groupthink” is hardly the domain of the rich or the poor, the
educated or the uneducated, the chattering classes or the unwashed masses. I
have seen groups of all sizes and kinds, where the pull of conformity drowns
out any critical voice, from the roar of the sports arena to the refined
intimacy of a fancy cocktail party. Our actions never exist in isolation. We
both allow ourselves to be easily influenced, and we also easily influence
others in turn.
I was
once taking a friend from out of town through a neighborhood of Boston called
the North End, which is known for its many fine Italian restaurants. It came
time to eat, and my friend seemed drawn to a place with a long line out front.
It was fascinating to see how the appearance of demand seemed to breed even greater
demand. His wife referred us to a restaurant guide, and insisted we follow the
opinion of the best food critics.
I
suggested a small place off the main road, for the simple reason that I had
eaten there a dozen times over the years, and had always been impressed by the
cooking. Until they took their first bite, they were deeply apprehensive of the
humble interior and wobbly tables.
They
still mention that meal to me many years later. “How did you know to go there?
What was the secret?”
There
was no secret wisdom at all, but I just knew what I liked, and I was not
interested in what the mobs of tourists or the snobs in the media told me was
best.
There is
a surreal irony, both beautiful and ridiculous, in the way we consider lemmings
as symbols of blind conformity. We have all heard, for example, that they will
commit mass suicide to control their populations. Naturalists roll their eyes
at this, and point out that while lemmings will indeed migrate in large groups,
and that some may die during such travels, they are hardly taking their own
lives.
Instead,
the myth about suicidal lemming conformity is itself the result of our own foolish
human conformity. Like so many other American children, I had seen an old
Disney documentary called White
Wilderness, which offered actual footage of the lemmings appearing to hurl
themselves off of a cliff. The filmmakers, however, had actually imported the
lemmings, herded them around, used some clever editing shots, and then
apparently even thrown a few off the cliff themselves. The lemmings were
pushed.
It took
the manipulation of an image on a screen to convince a generation of young
people that lemmings killed themselves, and those people told others, who told
others, and before we know it, the crush of conformity, the power of the herd,
is now about us, and not about those little animals. This is why Seneca warns
us that we risk deluding ourselves when we blindly follow every example. . . .
4. Rising
above the vulgar
When we are considering a happy life,
you cannot answer me as though after a division of the house, "this view
has most supporters;" because for that very reason it is the worse of the
two: matters do not stand so well with mankind that the majority should prefer
the better course. The more people do a thing, the worse it is likely to be.
Let us therefore inquire, not what is
most commonly done, but what is best for us to do, and what will establish us
in the possession of undying happiness, not what is approved of by the vulgar,
the worst possible exponents of truth.
By "the vulgar" I mean both
those who wear woolen cloaks and those who wear crowns; for I do not regard the
color of the clothes with which they are covered. I do not trust my eyes to
tell me what a man is: I have a better and more trustworthy light by which I
can distinguish what is true from what is false. Let the mind find out what is
good for the mind.
If a man ever allows his mind some
breathing space and has leisure for communing with himself, what truths he will
confess to himself, after having been put to the torture by his own self! . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 2 (tr Stewart)
It is
too easy to confuse what is popular with what is right, because we are quickly
carried away with impressions, because it requires far less effort to conform
than to judge for oneself, and because there is a lazy comfort in in the
security of the group.
I have
observed that a faction will often define itself even more by a hatred of the
opposition than a love of its own platform, and how much there can be a certain
malicious and exclusive glee in being part of “us” rather than part of “them”.
I was
fortunate enough to only spend a short time of my life tempted by the mentality
of the herd, first in matters of politics, and then in matters of religion. The
appeal quickly faded, because it all seemed more like acting in a play than
about living a life. I learned quickly that herd loyalty is far more emotional
than it is rational, and that the perspectives could change at a moment’s
notice, with the whims of fashion and the empty promises of demagogues.
Standing
back from the quarrels, one could see that the different sides were all selling
much the same pabulum, masked in slightly different flavors. The obedience to
the tribe had silenced a commitment to shared humanity.
The
vulgarity Seneca describes can be seen anywhere and everywhere, and it is
hardly defined by class or status. I have listened to oil workers in Oklahoma
worship their flags and guns just as often as I have listened to suburban
professionals in Boston exclude anyone who is not as properly diverse as they believe
themselves to be. What makes such displays vulgar is the exercise of ignorance
and vanity clothed in the appearance of enlightenment.
I am
best served to remember that a man is not defined by how he would wish to
appear to me, but by the merit of what he truly thinks and of what he actually does.
If I can peel away all the images and trappings, if I can look beneath the
manipulations and the hypocrisy, I will be left with nothing but the identity
of my own human nature, of a being ruled by reflection and understanding, and
how that is ordered to the Nature of all other things. Anything beyond this
becomes a diversion.
If I do
not allow myself to be distracted by the confusion of all the accidents, by
status, possessions, or popularity, I can come to perceive the essence, the
identity of a being that exists solely to live by the knowledge of what is true
and the love of what is good. The rest must fall away, revealing only that
purity, which is at the very root of our freedom and happiness.
5. To
take a Stoic Turn
. . . He will say, "Whatever I
have hitherto done I wish were undone. When I think over what I have said, I
envy dumb people. Whatever I have longed for seems to have been what my enemies
would pray to befall me.
“Good heaven, how far more endurable
what I have feared seems to be than what I have lusted after. I have been at
enmity with many men, and have changed my dislike of them into friendship, if
friendship can exist between bad men: yet I have not yet become reconciled to myself.
“I have striven with all my strength to
raise myself above the common herd, and to make myself remarkable for some
talent. What have I effected except to make myself a mark for the arrows of my
enemies, and show those who hate me where to wound me?
“Do you see those who praise your
eloquence, who covet your wealth, who court your favor, or who vaunt your
power? All these either are, or, which comes to the same thing, may be your enemies.
The number of those who envy you is as great as that of those who admire you;
why do I not rather seek for some good thing that I can use and feel, not one
that I can show?
“These good things which men gaze at in
wonder, which they crowd to see, which one points out to another with
speechless admiration, are outwardly brilliant, but within are miseries to
those who possess them.”
— Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 2 (tr Stewart)
What
begins to happen when I look past everything that is extraneous to only the
things that are essential? I won’t just see myself and my world from a slightly
different angle, but in many cases I will actually begin seeing it in a
completely opposite manner.
Once I
consider my happiness through my nature, and not from my circumstances, so many
aspects of the good and the bad will be flipped in my judgment. The things I
once desired become repugnant, and what I was once proud of is now a source of
shame. The goal is no longer about providing more for myself, but rather making more of myself, not appearing
good, but rather being good, and not
ruling the world, but ruling my own attitude about the world. The shift is starting
to think from the inside out, instead of from the outside in.
I have
myself found no clearer instance of this than our estimation of friends. As
soon as I acquire friends because of what they will do for me, such a
relationship is entirely relative and changeable. The difference between a
friend and an enemy will become as razor thin as the perception of convenience
or inconvenience. I believe Seneca is quite right to question whether
friendship can even exist between bad men, for in one sense, everyone is an
enemy, someone waiting to be used or opposed, to be treated as a means and
never as an end.
I once
knew a fellow who had been married three times, and he was quite proud of the
fact that the third was a charm. He was happy to explain that he had figured
out, through the experience of the first two wives, how to speak and act in
following the path of least resistance, and to receive what he expected. His
proof of this was the first two wives hadn’t lasted very long, but the he was
now approaching a major anniversary with the last one. “I won’t marry again if
this one turns out not to work after all,” he said. “It just won’t be worth it
for me.”
I was
prudent enough to bite my tongue, but I understood his thinking entirely, as I
had seen it so often before. The third wife had indeed lasted the longest, but
this was proof of nothing other than that she had pleased him the longest. If
she ceased to please him, then that relationship would also be over; she would
become as mocked and ridiculed as her predecessors. For now, however, she and
her children would be the perfect family on all the holiday cards and vacation
photos.
I know I
am on the right path with the Stoic Turn when I understand that desiring
everything praised and admired on the outside will be the death of me on the
inside. It isn’t the many things in this world, all of them beautiful in
themselves, or the many people I will meet, all of them worthy of love in
themselves, that are the problem, but the manner in which I approach them that
will make all the difference. As soon as I define myself by what I possess and
control, I have enslaved my character to appearance and utility.
6. What
to reach for?
Let us seek for some blessing, which
does not merely look fine, but is sound and good throughout alike, and most
beautiful in the parts which are least seen: let us unearth this. It is not far
distant from us; it can be discovered.
All that is necessary is to know
whether to stretch out your hand: but, as it is, we behave as though we were in
the dark, and reach out beyond what is nearest to us, striking as we do so
against the very things that we want.
However, that I may not draw you into
digressions, I will pass over the opinions of other philosophers, because it
would take a long time to state and confute them all: take ours.
When, however, I say "ours”, I do
not bind myself to any one of the chiefs of the Stoic school, for I too have a
right to form my own opinion. I shall, therefore, follow the authority of some
of them, but shall ask some others to discriminate their meaning: perhaps, when
after having reported all their opinions, I am asked for my own, I shall impugn
none of my predecessors' decisions, and shall say, "I will also add somewhat
to them.” . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 3 (tr Stewart)
I fondly
remember my newborn son reaching out his hand, and, like every new father, I
held out my own hand. He clenched onto my finger like a vise, and he would not
let go. I was very happy to oblige, and I could not even conceive of pulling
myself free.
I know,
the experts tell me that a newborn can’t see, has no sense of self, most
certainly can’t smile, and will grasp onto anything that comes his way. All of
this, modern science explains, is just a biological reaction.
That is
as it may well be, but such a biological reaction tells us most everything
about how we will all continue to grow, in body, in mind, and in spirit. In the
end, that same instinct defines everything about us. We all seek what is good,
in whatever way we can. It was no accident that the only thing that dragged my
son away from my finger was his mother’s milk.
He is
now much older, and he reaches still. He no longer reaches for my hand when he
feels fear, and he no longer reaches for his mother’s embrace when he desires
comfort. He is becoming his own man; he reaches for purpose and meaning in
everything that he does, but now he is learning to decide for himself. He can
see, he can feel, he can understand, and perhaps most apparently, he can smile
and he can frown.
I will
refuse, to the bitter end, to define my children by the social, political,
religious, and economic clubs they belong to. I will ask them to define themselves
by their own reason, and certainly not by whether they have pleased me, or whether
they have succeeded in the eyes of the world. I hope I can only help them to not
reach out blindly into the dark, but to have a sense to see clearly what is really
worth holding on to.
The
truth about our lives isn’t distant or obscure; it’s right there in front if
us, within us, if we only choose to see who we are. I was quite amazed to see
the privilege given to some of my wealthy peers, many hundreds of thousands of
dollars in entitlements, and the disadvantage suffered by some of my poorer
peers, many hundreds of thousand of dollars in need. The very problem, from day
one, was that we all assumed those many hundreds of thousands of dollars would
make any difference whatsoever. I ask myself, most every day, whether the
presence of wealth would have made me any better, or the presence of need actually
made me any worse?
Those
are not the things to reach for. Reach for what is near, reach for the truth
clear within the mind, and the love clear within the heart. Do not reach for a
career, or a ten year plan, or a twenty year plan, but reach for an immediate
living plan. Reach for what is entirely within your power, to be a decent human
being, who seeks the truth without bias, and who loves his neighbor without
prejudice.
Through
all of this, avoid “–isms”. Seneca considers himself a Stoic, but he will most
certainly not define himself by this or that school, or movement, or
fashionable trend. He will find the truth wherever it may be found, not at the
expense of one, but for the fulfillment of all.
7. Follow
Nature
. . . Meanwhile I follow Nature, which
is a point upon which every one of the Stoic philosophers are agreed: true
wisdom consists in not departing from Nature and in molding our conduct
according to her laws and model.
A happy life, therefore, is one which
is in accordance with its own nature, and cannot be brought about unless in the
first place the mind be sound and remain so without interruption, and next, be
bold and vigorous, enduring all things with most admirable courage, suited to
the times in which it lives, careful of the body and its accessories, yet not
troublesomely careful.
It must also set due value upon all the
things which adorn our lives, without over-estimating any one of them, and must
be able to enjoy the bounty of Fortune without becoming her slave.
You understand without my mentioning it
that an unbroken calm and freedom ensue, when we have driven away all those
things which either excite us or alarm us: for in the place of sensual
pleasures and those slight perishable matters which are connected with the
basest crimes, we thus gain an immense, unchangeable, equable joy, together
with peace, calmness and greatness of mind, and kindliness: for all savagery is
a sign of weakness.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 3 (tr Stewart)
Now surely
this appeal to Nature seems to be the perfect cop-out. Whatever could that
possibly mean? We live in a time where metaphysics is about crystals and past
lives, where ethics is about the whims of social propriety, and where happiness
is just about feeling good about ourselves. Nature becomes an all-inclusive
term for whatever we happen to want at the moment.
The
Ancients in general, and the Stoics in particular, were far more specific in
this regard; they understood Nature not as a vague idea, but as a clearly
defined principle. Aristotle was never the most poetic of philosophers, but he
explained it as follows in Book II of the Physics:
Nature
is a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest, in
that to which it belongs primarily, in virtue of itself, and not
in virtue of another.
The
nature of anything is simply what it does according to its very identity. A
heavy thing, by nature, will fall, and a light thing, by nature, will rise. A
plant will grow, an animal will sense, and a man will think.
There is
no deep mystery here, no obscurity, and no speaking in tongues. Ask yourself
what it means to be a human being, and then consider what such a being does to
complete itself. A man is composed of matter, as all sensible things are. He
has a principle of nutrition, growth, and reproduction, as all living things
do. Finally, he has a mind and the power of free choice, which allow him to
understand his world and his own actions, and to determine his actions for
himself. Now that which is more complete is greater than what which is less
complete, and it is more complete for anything to rule itself than to be ruled.
No hemming
and hawing is required. It is immediately clear that a man is not the sum of
his accidents, but rather the fulfillment of his essence. I was never put on
this Earth to be determined by what is outside of myself, but to determine, by
my own judgment, how I will make something of myself.
However
much I feel pleasure or pain, that is not the life of a man, but the life of a
beast.
However
much I possess or do not possess, that is not the life of a man, but the life of
an accountant’s ledger.
However
much I am loved or despised, that is not the life of a man, but the life of an
opinion poll.
Yet once
I possess a clear understanding of the good inherent in all things, and I have
acted with that knowledge, I am now a man. My humanity is intact.
This
requires a willingness to see things as they are in themselves, and not as I
would want them to be. It requires a willingness to act for the sake of both
myself and others, not for my sake at the expense of others. It requires seeing
my own nature as part of all things, of all of Nature, and not seeing myself as
being above all things.
The
soundness of my mind is wisdom. The soundness of my choices is courage. The
soundness of my passions is temperance. The soundness of my respect for others
is justice.
Happiness
is not the pleasure that comes from conquest or gratification, but the joy that
proceeds from thinking and acting with Nature, and never acting against it.
That is freedom, that is contentment, and that is peace.
I am
not, by my own nature, a savage beast, but a person, one whose very nature
tells him how he must live. I must choose to consider all of Fortune rightly,
and never allow Fortune to rule me.
8. Discerning
the highest good
Our highest good may also be defined
otherwise, that is to say, the same idea may be expressed in different
language. Just as the same army may at one time be extended more widely, at
another contracted into a smaller compass, and may either be curved towards the
wings by a depression in the line of the center, or drawn up in a straight
line, while, in whatever figure it be arrayed, its strength and loyalty remain
unchanged; so also our definition of the highest good may in some cases be
expressed diffusely and at great length, while in others it is put into a short
and concise form.
Thus, it will come to the same thing,
if I say "The highest good is a mind which despises the accidents of
fortune, and takes pleasure in virtue.” Or "It is an unconquerable
strength of mind, knowing the world well, gentle in its dealings, showing great
courtesy and consideration for those with whom it is brought into
contact."
Or we may choose to define it by
calling that man happy who knows good and bad only in the form of good or bad
minds, who worships honor, and is satisfied with his own virtue, who is neither
puffed up by good fortune nor cast down by evil fortune, who knows no other
good than that which he is able to bestow upon himself, whose real pleasure
lies in despising pleasures. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 4 (tr Stewart)
The
ignorant man cares neither for words nor for meaning. The scholar often cares
for words at the expense of meaning. The true philosopher loves words because
they indicate meaning.
There
isn’t always one right wording, since varying forms of definitions will express
different aspects and strengths, and different degrees of breadth and depth. Arrange
your army in whatever formation you wish, but it is still the same army.
I would
always enjoy reading Aristotle on happiness with students, and though his
philosophy is from a different tradition than that of the Stoics, I was pleased
to see how some students would have that moment of insight, where however we
ordered the words, it became clear to them that happiness was essentially
measured by what we did, and not by what happened to us.
Aristotle,
for example, offers a very precise definition:
Happiness is the activity of a
rational soul, according to complete virtue, and determined over a complete
life.
Now all
of that is quite a mouthful, and can certainly seem confusing and obscure. More
academically inclined students may take this apart, and relate all the pieces
to the overall argument of the chapter, that happiness is always an end and
never a means, and that it must therefore be something complete and
self-sufficient, or that we can come to know what is good for a human being by
considering the function of human nature. Such discussions are the sorts of
things that inspire us bookish teachers, especially if we can dabble in the
subtleties of the original Greek.
Every so
often I would have the pleasure of such an involved and lively discussion,
though one of my favorite moments came when I noticed a quiet and reserved
student staring out the window and smiling. I wanted to pull her into the
conversation. I asked her if any of the definition was helpful.
“Yes,
because it sounds like he’s really just saying two things. Happiness is about
living, and it’s about living well.” The budding Greek scholars were suddenly
silent, because the unassuming student had it all in a nutshell.
Notice
also, of course, how this is hardly much different from a Stoic view, or from the
different wordings that Seneca suggests. Happiness proceeds from the excellence
of my actions, and not from my circumstances. This is why the happy man is
strong from within. He expresses love and concern for his neighbors, out of the
very conviction that his character will define him. We might consider many
different parts and aspects of a happy life, but it remains one and the same
thing throughout.
I was
once part of a similar sort of discussion, this one not even in the formal
context of a class, where we were trying to come to an agreeable definition of
honor. Seneca uses it, for example, in one of his possible definitions. Now
honor seems quite a noble word, but it can be used in very different ways.
The
conversation was quickly unraveling, because some people thought seeking honor
was an expression of good moral character, and others thought it was the
pursuit of vanity. It took someone only a moment to clarify what was shared,
and where there was divergence: “Honor is about respect or credit. Now a good
man is honorable if he acts out of respect for his own conscience. A bad man is
honorable if he lets his life be determined only by the respect other people
give him.”
I don’t
think Seneca, or any Stoic, or any philosopher, could have put it any better. Let
what is good in life proceed from yourself, and not what you receive from the
world.
9. Beyond
fear or desire
. . . If you choose to pursue this
digression further, you can put this same idea into many other forms, without
impairing or weakening the meaning.
For what prevents our saying that a
happy life consists in a mind which is free, upright, undaunted, and steadfast,
beyond the influence of fear or desire, which thinks nothing good except honor,
and nothing bad except blame, and regards everything else as a mass of mean
details which can neither add anything to nor take anything away from the
happiness of life, but which come and go without either increasing or
diminishing the highest good?
A man of these principles, whether he
wills it or not, must be accompanied by a continual cheerfulness, a high
happiness, which comes indeed from on high because he delights in what he has,
and desires no greater pleasures than those which his home affords.
Is he not right in allowing these to
turn the scale against petty, ridiculous and short-lived movements of his wretched
body? On the day on which he becomes proof against pleasure he also becomes
proof against pain.
See, on the other hand, how evil and
guilty a slavery the man is forced to serve who is dominated in turn by
pleasures and pains, those most untrustworthy and passionate of masters. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 4 (tr Stewart)
I need
only reflect on how much of my life has been foolishly determined by fear and
desire, in avoiding pain and in seeking pleasure, to recognize the root of my
weakness. It is not the feelings of pleasure and pain that are flawed in
themselves, but rather allowing myself to be ruled by them. The Stoic does not
deny his passions, but he understands how to put them in their proper place.
Being steadfast proceeds not from brute strength, or from any heartless
indifference, but simply from learning to care more for what is superior, and
less for what is inferior.
It is my
own estimation that will make all the difference. We are surely all familiar
with that liberating sense, when we hardly desire something that we know is bad
for us, and we hardly fear something that we know can never hurt us. I am not
drawn to accumulating many possessions, or seeking the company of untrustworthy
people, because I know there is nothing good in them. I have learned not to
fear being alone, because I know I always have myself.
I must
apply that same standard to anything and everything that is part of my
circumstances. I have no power over them, and should therefore hardly worry
about their coming and going. I do have power over my own judgments, values,
and choices, and I can remember that my own good rests only in the exercise of
my character. Pleasure and pain will be as they will be, but the effect they
may have depends only upon how much I care for them.
Becoming
upright in my own principles is the source of my freedom from hurt and want,
which in turn yields the fruits of joy and cheerfulness. I have known many people
who struggle to be good, and who are sometimes angry or dissatisfied with their
failures; I have often counted myself as such a man. I have, however, yet to
meet someone who has rightly made the Stoic Turn who does not also display the
deepest contentment under all types of conditions. This is not because he is
oblivious to pleasure and pain, but because he has learned to gauge their meaning
and importance.
The
slavery that follows from being mastered by our passions is only a servitude of
our own choices, and we are, in turn, the only sources of our own emancipation.
10. Escaping
into freedom
. . . We must, therefore, escape from
them into freedom.
This nothing will bestow upon us except
contempt of Fortune. But if we attain to this, then there will dawn upon us
those invaluable blessings, the repose of a mind that is at rest in a safe
haven, its lofty imaginings, its great and steady delight at casting out errors
and learning to know the truth, its courtesy, and its cheerfulness.
In all of these we shall take delight,
not regarding them as good things in themselves, but as proceeding from the
proper good of man.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 4 (tr Stewart)
We often
think of freedom in terms of being free from
something, of having a limitation removed. We can also think of freedom in
terms of being free in something, of
embracing a responsibility or commitment. I find both of these aspects helpful
in the practice of Stoicism, because each of these is only fully possible
through the other.
I must
learn not to depend upon Fortune, but I must cast aside what is unreliable and
fleeting by also pursuing what is truly fulfilling and constant. I am not just
defined by what is bad for me, by what I should avoid, but also by what is good
for me, by what I should seek. It is only the complete embrace of Nature that
allows me to escape from Fortune.
As a
child, being told what I shouldn’t do
sometimes frustrated me. A begrudging compliance could only be transformed into
a willful commitment when I understood what I should do, and why it was worth doing. That I should not lie,
cheat, or steal only completely made sense if I also knew that I needed to
love. If I need to run away from one thing, I also need something else to be
running toward. Don’t just tell me how not to be bad, but show me how to be
good.
Learning
to be accountable for my own thoughts and deeds brings with it many benefits. It
brings with it a place of rest, a peace of mind, and a sense of profound
contentment. The satisfaction of feeling
good is, however, not itself the end, but a consequence of that purpose, of being good. The very reason a life
virtue is satisfying is precisely because I am not seeking satisfaction alone,
divorced from any right responsibility and action.
One of
the greatest trials of my life was caring for someone who, it turned out, had
developed only half of a conscience. Right or wrong were measured solely by
pursuing praise and avoiding blame from others, and were determined entirely by
external rewards and punishments. I was met with a blank stare if I suggested
that doing right was its own reward.
The
whole experience taught me that things in life are never good just because they
are pleasant, but they are rightly pleasant because they are good. Once I have
my own wires crossed regarding the good and the pleasant, I am caring only for
a freedom from consequences, and not a freedom in character.
11. A
man, not a rock
Since I have begun to make my
definitions without a too strict adherence to the letter, a man may be called
"happy" who, thanks to reason, has ceased either to hope or to fear.
But rocks also feel neither fear nor sadness, nor do cattle, yet no one would
call those things happy which cannot comprehend what happiness is.
With them you may class men whose dull
nature and want of self-knowledge reduces them to the level of cattle, mere
animals. There is no difference between the one and the other, because the
latter have no reason, while the former have only a corrupted form of it,
crooked and cunning to their own hurt. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 5 (tr Stewart)
A rock
has a body, like a man, but the body of a rock has no life, no feeling, and no
thought. An animal has a body with life and with feeling, like a man, but the
life and feeling of an animal is not ordered and guided by understanding.
Now the
rock or the beast are hardly flawed in their lack of feeling or understanding,
because the presence of awareness or mind is not a part of their natures. We
should consider something deficient not when any characteristic is absent, but
when a characteristic is absent that rightly ought to be present. A rock and an
animal are not made to think, and we do not blame them when they fail to do so.
A human being, on the other hand, chooses to cast away his very identity when
he chooses not to think.
I must
remember, therefore, that the happy life, where I am no longer troubled by hope
or by fear, does not proceed from not thinking about hopes and fears, but comes
rather from understanding them rightly, and no longer allowing myself to be
ruled by them. Once I know what is good for me, I will no longer be burdened by
hope for the things beyond my power, and once I know what is bad for me, I will
no longer be burdened by fear of the things beyond my power. I have become
impervious to both, because I care for neither.
While
the rock or the animal simply cannot think at all, a thoughtless man is still
able to think, but neglects or perverts that power. I see all the injustice and
hurt around me, each and every day, that follows from failing to reflect upon
the meaning and purpose of our actions. I am myself delinquent, however, if my
judgment is itself condescending or dismissive, because I can be well aware of
how and why I have been thoughtless myself. It is indeed wrong for us to be
thoughtless, but it is also right for us to then correct this by perceiving the
causes.
I have
been thoughtless when I have cared for myself at the expense of others. I
partly recognize my own worth, but I have divorced it from the good of the
whole, and I have removed my nature from all of Nature.
I have
been thoughtless when I have defined myself by all the circumstances around me,
and not by my own choices and actions. I have placed good and evil in
everything on the outside, and I have conversely neglected to respect myself.
I have
been thoughtless when I have grown tired of effort, disappointment, or loss,
and I choose to simply shut myself down. When feeling and thinking seem to
hurt, it may appear that it is best not to feel or think at all.
In
whatever way my decision has been disordered, by dismissing others, by
dismissing myself, or by dismissing both myself and others, I have abandoned a
necessary reflection on who I am, and why I am here. This is the greatest of
all human losses, because it is the loss of humanity itself.
When I
am no longer thinking about how I am living, there is no longer any worth in
living. It is only the recovery of consciousness that will restore life.
12. Tickled
day and night
. . . For no one can be styled happy
who is beyond the influence of truth, and consequently a happy life is
unchangeable, and is founded upon a true and trustworthy discernment; for the
mind is uncontaminated and freed from all evils only when it is able to escape
not merely from wounds but also from scratches, when it will always be able to
maintain the position which it has taken up, and defend it even against the
angry assaults of Fortune.
For with regard to sensual pleasures,
though they were to surround one on every side, and use every means of assault,
trying to win over the mind by caresses and making trial of every conceivable
stratagem to attract either our entire selves or our separate parts, yet what
mortal that retains any traces of human origin would wish to be tickled day and
night, and, neglecting his mind, to devote himself to bodily enjoyments?
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 5 (tr Stewart)
I have learned
to see the conditions of my life as always being subject to change, sometimes
slow and subtle, sometimes sudden and drastic, but almost always in ways I could
never have expected. If someone had told me thirty years ago what I would end
up seeing, what I would be asked to live through, or where I would be now, I
would surely have laughed it off.
Hindsight
now allows me to view such things more openly and broadly, but I must still
admit to feeling very uncertain about what can still come. Nothing about the
world around me should be taken as a given, and anything can be completely
different in the briefest moment.
Because
the world will never be the same from day to day does not, however, mean that
there cannot be something unchanging and constant about my own thinking and
living. What can remain stable about myself, if I only so choose, is standing
firm in my sense of what is right and wrong, and the way in which I go about
estimating anything and everything in my circumstances.
The
happy man is not himself literally unmoving, since he himself always acts, but
rather he does not allow those actions to be determined by the whims of good or
bad Fortune. He rules himself, and he navigates his own way through both calm and
stormy seas. He knows what he is about, and he knows that, whether he will live
for a long or a short time, no one can take that from him.
The
details hardly matter anymore, but what I once saw as the happiest moment of my
life was not really happy, because it was just about a deeply pleasant
convergence of events. What I later saw as the most miserable moment of my life
was not really miserable, because it was just about a deeply unpleasant
convergence of events. I felt loved in one, and abandoned in another. I now see
that I would have been much better served to be the same man at both times,
instead of becoming two totally different men.
Whenever
I pursued a path of life where I longed for pleasure and ran from pain, I was
always so sure that I was firmly in control of what I did. It seemed easy to
pick one and reject the other, but I had already unwittingly abandoned any
possibility of self-mastery. This had occurred because I estimated my value by
what happened, not by what I did with what happened.
I love
how Seneca compares constant pleasure seeking to being constantly tickled. A
pleasant sensation quickly gives way to the recognition that we are powerless
in the face of it, that we no longer control ourselves, but that we are letting
ourselves be controlled. The constancy of character surrenders to the flux of
feelings.
As a child,
my father tried to teach me how to not feel ticklish. “It’s simple,” he said.
“Don’t think of someone else tickling you, but imagine you’re tickling
yourself.” I never could quite get the hang of that particular ability, which
seemed like some profound Zen wisdom or Jedi mind trick, but I do understand
the principle in so many aspects of life. Rule what is unchanging within
yourself, or let yourself be ruled by everything that changes.
13. Pleasures
of the mind
"But," says our adversary,
"the mind also will have pleasures of its own." Let it have them,
then, and let it sit in judgment over luxury and pleasures; let it indulge
itself to the full in all those matters which give sensual delights.
Then let it look back upon what it
enjoyed before, and with all those faded sensualities fresh in its memory let
it rejoice and look eagerly forward to those other pleasures which it
experienced long ago, and intends to experience again, and while the body lies
in helpless repletion in the present, let it send its thoughts onward towards
the future, and take stock of its hopes.
All this will make it appear, in my
opinion, yet more wretched, because it is insanity to choose evil instead of
good. Now no insane person can be happy, and no one can be sane if he regards
what is injurious as the highest good and strives to obtain it.
The happy man, therefore, is he who can
make a right judgment in all things. He is happy who in his present
circumstances, whatever they may be, is satisfied and on friendly terms with
the conditions of his life. That man is happy, when his reason recommends to
him the whole posture of his affairs.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 6 (tr Stewart)
The “adversary”
here is the Epicurean. You need not worry about the history of it all right
here, but you already know him, as the one who tells you to maximize your
pleasure, and to minimize your pain.
Back
then, it was Epicurus and his followers who defined you as a creature of
desire. Hume, Bentham, and Mill kept that standard going. We now no longer need
fancy philosophers to tell us that whatever feels good, is good. We now have
corporate advertising to do that thinking for us, and which convinces us that
the more of their products we consume, the happier we will be.
It would
be a mistake to misrepresent the Epicurean as a mindless glutton, just as it
would a mistake to misrepresent the Stoic as an emotionless mind. While the
Epicurean doesn’t denigrate thinking, and the Stoic doesn’t denigrate feeling,
the important difference between them is one of priority.
For the
Epicurean, man’s highest good is about pleasure, about good feeling, and all
other things must be ordered to that end. For the Stoic, man’s highest good is
about virtue, about right action, and all other things must be ordered to that
end. In the simplest sense, it’s about the difference between feeling good and being good.
There
are times when Seneca can find common ground with the Epicureans, but in this
most basic matter his opposition is very clear. Man is indeed a creature that
feels pleasure and pain, but without the mind to judge soundly between what is
true or false, what is right or wrong, no life can be considered good, or
happy.
But
surely, the Epicurean might say, the reason we pursue thinking is because it
provides us with pleasure, and the mind therefore becomes the means by which we
acquire those feelings of satisfaction?
I always
suspect that Seneca takes something very seriously when his style becomes
sarcastic, and this passage is no exception. By all means, he tells us, treat
your intellect simply as a tool to pursue pleasure. What will your judgment
tell you? You will look back at the faded pleasures you have lost, and you will
entertain ridiculous hopes of somehow getting them again. In the meantime, you
are stuck in the middle, between memory and expectation. All this time, your
mind will be reminding you how shallow those feelings really are, and how they
were never really satisfying at all, because they always left you wanting more
and more.
The
mind, Seneca tells us, would hardly ever recommend the life of pleasure as
worthwhile, because the mind would clearly discern how empty and foolish such a
life truly is. Only an insane man, a mindless man, would ever want to acquire
what does him harm, and the most basic common sense teaches us that the pursuit
of passion divorced from knowledge will never do us any good.
I need
to think only of the most damaging choices I have ever made, and what they all
shared in common was that they were all about feeling right, not doing right.
If I had used my mind rightly, I would have spotted the difference right away. I
would have been at peace with myself and with my world, not tossed around by my
circumstances.
I once
met a fellow who insisted he knew me better than I knew myself, and told me
that the only reason I was so interested in philosophy was because it made me
feel good. “Hey, I think it’s fun to get drunk and have sex, you think it’s fun
to read a book. You and I aren’t really that different.” I smiled and bought
him a drink, wondering within myself how long he could keep this up until he
hit rock bottom.
No, he
and I were quite different, not because we liked to do different things, but
because we were starting from two opposing premises about what made life worth
living. We had our heads and our guts stacked differently.
14. Pleasure
and virtue 1
Even those very people who declare the highest
good to be in the belly, see what a dishonorable position they have assigned to
it: and therefore they say that pleasure cannot be parted from virtue, and that
no one can either live honorably without living cheerfully, nor yet live cheerfully
without living honorably.
I do not see how these very different
matters can have any connection with one another. What is there, I pray you, to
prevent virtue existing apart from pleasure? Of course the reason is that all
good things derive their origin from virtue, and therefore even those things,
which you cherish and seek for, come originally from its roots.
Yet, if they were entirely inseparable,
we should not see some things to be pleasant, but not honorable, and others
most honorable indeed, but hard and only to be attained by suffering.
Add to this, that pleasure visits the
basest lives, but virtue cannot co-exist with an evil life. Yet some unhappy
people are not without pleasure, no, it is owing to pleasure itself that they
are unhappy; and this could not take place if pleasure had any connection with
virtue, whereas virtue is often without pleasure, and never stands in need of
it. Why do you put together two things which are unlike and even incompatible
one with another?. . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 7 (tr Stewart)
Let us
please not assume that pleasure and virtue are in a necessary conflict with one
another, but let us also please not assume that they are one and the same
thing. Seneca, like any good Stoic, does not wish to deny us any pleasure in
life, and he certainly does not wish us any pain. He just wants us to never
confuse pleasure and virtue. They are certainly related to one another, but
they are not interchangeable.
Whether
we recognize it or not, we live in a very Epicurean age. Ask most anyone what
it means to be happy, and he will likely tell you that it’s all about a pleasant
feeling. I have long since learned not to bicker about this, but to quietly
practice my life in a very different way.
I am a
bit troubled when someone tells me that he is happy with his wife because she
always makes him feel good. I wonder if he is being honest with himself,
because love is most certainly not always fun. I also wonder if he has defined
love by what is done to him, and not by what he does.
I remain
convinced that a good man will ultimately find a certain pleasure, in my
estimation the deepest pleasure there can ever be, in the knowledge that he has
lived well. Yet he requires no rewards, and no recognition. He does not do what
is right because it makes him feel good, but only because it is right. The
satisfaction is a consequence, and not the end itself. He may well feel pain in
so many other ways, and he may suffer terribly, but he does not confuse the
awareness of his own character with the gratification of his desires.
The
value of any feeling is only as good as the awareness and action from which it
proceeds. I have known many people, myself included, who have felt pleasure
without being good at all, or have been good without feeling any pleasure at
all. Some of the most disgusting people seem to enjoy their depravity, at least
for the moment, and some of the best people will gladly suffer the greatest
pain.
I have
never thought of myself as a brave man, or even really as a good man; I have
long been in that greyness where I somehow know enough what I should do, but I
usually don’t know enough to actually do it.
I was
once waiting for a taxi, in a part of town I probably shouldn’t have been in to
begin with. Down the street, I saw a bunch of fellows pushing someone around,
and grabbing at the pockets of his jacket. I desperately wanted to look the
other way, but something clicked in me. I walked over, and played the best
Boston Irishman I could. There was much cussing and bravado on my part, though
I am a pale, weak, and sickly creature.
What
happened next was what I suspected would happen, but not what I wanted to
happen. The original victim scuttled off, but now I was the victim. They wanted
blood, and they got it. I was pushed down before I could even think, my head
hit the pavement, and I felt foot after foot kicking me all over. I curled into
a ball, and it hurt like hell.
They
grew tired of their kicking, and wandered off after some choice words, and the
placing of a big glob of warm spit on my face.
How did
I feel? Did any of it give me pleasure? Not at all. My body hurt in a way I had
never felt before, and my ego was ground into the dirt beyond recognition.
I would still
like to think that I did something good, and that I wasn’t just being prideful.
Let’s assume, for the sake of argument, that this was the case. Nothing about
it felt good at all, in any way whatsoever. It still doesn’t feel good, and
it’s one of about a dozen experiences I’ve had that still give me nightmares
many years later.
There
are many times in life where we are called to live well, while still knowing
full well that we’re not going to enjoy it. A wise man, my old priest and confessor,
once put this in the simplest of terms: “Don’t expect the world to make your
life pleasant. Expect yourself to try and make the world right.”
15. Pleasure
and virtue 2
. . . Virtue is a lofty quality,
sublime, royal, unconquerable, untiring. Pleasure is low, slavish, weakly,
perishable; its haunts and homes are the brothel and the tavern. You will meet
virtue in the temple, the marketplace, the senate house, manning the walls,
covered with dust, sunburnt, horny-handed. You will find pleasure skulking out
of sight, seeking for shady nooks at the public baths, hot chambers, and places
which dread the visits of the magistrates, soft, effeminate, reeking of wine
and perfumes, pale or perhaps painted and made up with cosmetics.
The highest good is immortal: it knows
no ending, and does not admit of either satiety or regret. For a right-thinking
mind never alters or becomes hateful to itself, nor do the best things ever
undergo any change, but pleasure dies at the very moment when it charms us
most. It has no great scope, and therefore it soon cloys and wearies us, and
fades away as soon as its first impulse is over.
Indeed, we cannot depend upon anything
whose nature is to change. Consequently it is not even possible that there
should be any solid substance in that which comes and goes so swiftly, and
which perishes by the very exercise of its own functions, for it arrives at a
point at which it ceases to be, and even while it is beginning always keeps its
end in view.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 7 (tr Stewart)
I have
never been an uptight or prudish person, a moral curmudgeon or an ideological
stick in the mud. I do not believe that passions must be denied in order to
live my life well, and I am saddened whenever I see people who hate their own
appetites, thinking they can only be good if they are cold, joyless, and
heartless. I have never agreed with the morality of Immanuel Kant.
I hardly
knew what to say when a very proper man once told me that he had many children
because it was his duty to God and to society. “What about all the wonderful
pleasure there is in making them,” I asked with a grin, “and all the wonderful
pleasure there is in sharing your life with them?” He was aghast. Marriage, he
told me, was about making more babies, even it was deeply dirty and distasteful
to do so.
At the
same time, I have little patience for the lecher, the glutton, or the
money-grubber. I recently somehow struggled my way through a conversation with
a man who offered me a list of all the attractive celebrities he wanted to have
sex with. It hardly occurred to him that they might not wish to sleep with him,
of course, but I did mange to ask him why this was so desirable. “Hey, I’ll
have my fun, even if I have to put a bag over her head, and maybe I’ll get some
alimony out of it!” He found it funny, and I found it disgusting.
The good
life is never about denying pleasure for its own sake, or seeking pleasure for
its own sake. Pleasure is, in itself, indifferent. Some feelings are good,
because they follow from good actions, and some feelings are bad, because they
follow from bad actions. I am not just a beast, and I am not just a mind in a
vat. I am a human being because I can think about what is good, and also
understand why some things are indeed worth enjoying.
Seneca
may appear a bit uptight here, but hard experience has taught me that he is
right on the mark. I distinctly recall my senior year in college, and all of
the things I did because they just seemed fun. The shame was not in the fun,
but in what I did to get there.
A few
weeks before I graduated, I was sitting in the sleaziest bar you can imagine, with
all of my supposed friends completely drunk, and the lost love of my life giving
an erotic backrub to a complete stranger. I felt sick, not just because I had
too much to drink, or because my girl was a tramp, but because I suddenly saw
who I was becoming.
I told
myself that I would, of course, return to a life of propriety the next day, but
that was an illusion. I would simply continue to use and abuse others, not in
the crudeness of a watering hole, but in the fancy environment of a
professional life. The trappings were different, but the lifestyle was the
same.
I always
remind myself that there is a difference between love and lust. The former
gives, and the latter only takes. The different places and different situations
Seneca describes are defined by the presence or absence of love and lust.
The
pathetic irony has always been that I may seek to possess, consume, or enjoy,
but as soon as I have done so, I immediately want more. Pleasure itself will
never satisfy, because it is itself never complete. Lust craves, but Love rests.
16. The
guide and the companion
What answer are we to make to the
reflection that pleasure belongs to good and bad men alike, and that bad men
take as much delight in their shame as good men in noble things?
This was why the ancients bade us lead
the highest, not the most pleasant life, in order that pleasure might not be
the guide but the companion of a right-thinking and honorable mind; for it is
Nature whom we ought to make our guide: let our reason watch her, and be
advised by her.
To live happily, then, is the same
thing as to live according to Nature: what this may be, I will explain. If we
guard the endowments of the body and the advantages of Nature with care and
fearlessness, as things soon to depart and given to us only for a day; if we do
not fall under their dominion, nor allow ourselves to become the slaves of what
is no part of our own being; if we assign to all bodily pleasures and external
delights the same position which is held by auxiliaries and light-armed troops
in a camp; if we make them our servants, not our masters—then and then only are
they of value to our minds. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 8 (tr Stewart)
Again,
happiness isn’t measured by pleasure or pain, because both the good man and the
wicked man will each feel different sorts of pleasures, for different sorts of
reasons. Seneca understands that the very exercise of philosophy will collapse
if there is no higher way to determine whether feelings are good or bad.
There
are many things in life that will always be there with us, but some of them
will accompany us as companions, while others will lead us a guides. Some will
walk next to us, and others will go out ahead. A life lived in harmony with Nature
will be one where these different roles are rightly distinguished, where I allow
my reason to be my guide, and where my pleasures are my companions. It will be
the judgment of the former that will determine the benefit of the latter.
So it
must be in all things, such that all of the conditions of my life are directed
by the guidance of the mind. I may receive a pleasure of the body, or some
wealth, or the esteem of others, but I will know what to make of these changing
situations if I know where I should be going, and how I should be living.
Fortune is fickle, and as soon as I depend upon her, I am enslaved to her.
Nature offers a deeper permanence of meaning to all of these things that are
passing, and the apprehension of Nature provides a constancy of purpose.
For many
years, I enjoyed the pleasures of cigarettes, because I craved the numbing
relaxation that came along with the consumption of nicotine. It didn’t take me
long to perceive how this was harmful to both my body and to my mind. The constant
shortness of breath that soon became a ritual of morning hacking, and the
mental obsession with getting to that next smoke caused me hurt, but I could
only think of being consumed by that brief feeling where the world cut into me
just a little but less. It was killing my body, and enslaving my thinking,
because I was making pleasure my master, and not my companion.
No
amount of brute willpower or clever cures ever really worked for me, until I
had the sense to apply Stoic practice to my daily addiction. After many years
of wallowing, I stopped smoking cigarettes from one day to another, and the
only thing that worked for me was a form of making my reason lead the way, and
letting my feelings walk alongside.
After a
prudent pause, I did something that flew in the face of contemporary fashion,
and I took an interest in the art of smoking a pipe. Now our unbridled hatred
of tobacco tells us that the evil weed must be removed entirely from society,
but the untrendy Stoic in me thought of it a bit differently.
I found
that I could actually enjoy the occasional pipe of fine tobacco, not greedily drawing
the smoke into my lungs, but sipping at it in contemplation. For me, this was
no different than the man who can find enjoyment in a single tumbler of fine whiskey,
and who does not need to guzzle a whole bottle of rotgut.
Nothing
given by Nature is evil, but only our abuse of things is evil. What makes
moderation so distinct from excess or denial is the understanding of whether my
mind rules a pleasure, or whether the pleasure rules me. It is no different
with, food, drink, sex, money, fame, or power.
I would
never suggest simply replacing cigarettes with a pipe as a remedy, because
fixing ourselves has nothing to do with how much of something we enjoy, or of
what certain kind, or in what specific manner. It has everything to do with
discerning the greater and the lesser.
17. Falling
back upon oneself
. . . A man should be unbiased and not
to be conquered by external things: he ought to admire himself alone, to feel
confidence in his own spirit, and so to order his life as to be ready alike for
good or for bad fortune.
Let not his confidence be without
knowledge, nor his knowledge without steadfastness. Let him always abide by
what he has once determined, and let there be no erasure in his doctrines. It
will be understood, even though I need not say it, that such a man will be
tranquil and composed in his demeanor, high-minded and courteous in his
actions.
Let reason be encouraged by the senses
to seek for the truth, and draw its first principles from there. Indeed, it has
no other base of operations or place from which to start in pursuit of truth:
it must fall back upon itself.
Even the all-embracing universe, and
God who is its guide, extends Himself forth into outward things, and yet
altogether returns from all sides back to Himself. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 8 (tr Stewart)
There is
a grave danger, especially in our age of egoism, of misunderstanding
self-reliance, what it truly means to fall back upon oneself. The crucial
distinction, I think, must come from whether we see ourselves as a source of
good, or as the end of good. A decent man recognizing that he is responsible
for himself, and depending upon his own character, acts for the sake of all of
Nature. He shares his good with others. A wicked man, in contrast, believing
that the world is responsible to him, and depending upon his own desires, acts
as if Nature exists for his sake. He expects to receive all other goods.
It is tragic,
of course, that the selfishness of the arrogant man is hardly strong or
confident at all. Such selfishness is weak, because it expects and demands that
the world provide for him. The arrogant man does not rely on himself, but relies
on everything else. He is actually a slave to Fortune, and not its master.
True
self-reliance means trusting only on one’s own merits, and only such a life can
rise above the shifting circumstances of Fortune. It is an attitude of service,
and not of being served. The beauty of this is that I will only become great
within myself when I do not expect the world to treat me greatly, and I will
immediately become weak within myself when I offer the world my list of
conditions and demands.
I have
learned to suspect someone may be self-serving, instead of self-reliant, when
his words and actions reveal a desire for leverage over others. He defines his
success by things he has conquered, or expects to conquer, rather than by
conquering himself. He is quick to criticize and blame his neighbor, but he
does not criticize or blame himself. His words often go sideways, and they are
rarely direct. His strength is not in being content with his own thoughts and
deeds, but in making the thoughts and deeds of others appear to be weak.
We may
express this concept in whatever philosophical or religious manner we wish, but
there is something Divine about true self-reliance. The Ancients often spoke of
the degrees of perfection in terms of how much or how little something moved
itself, by its level of sufficiency. By such a standard, God is pure
perfection, because He depends upon nothing beyond himself, and by comparison a
self-reliant and self-sufficient man, who always falls back upon himself,
shares and participates in that which is Godlike.
18. Agreement,
unity, and virtue
. . . Let our mind do the same thing:
when, following its bodily senses it has by means of them sent itself forth
into the things of the outward world, let it remain still their master and its
own.
By this means we shall obtain a
strength and an ability which are united and allied together, and shall derive
from it that reason which never halts between two opinions, nor is dull in
forming its perceptions, beliefs, or convictions.
Such a mind, when it has ranged itself
in order, made its various parts agree together, and, if I may so express
myself, harmonized them, has attained to the highest good, for it has nothing
evil or hazardous remaining, nothing to shake it or make it stumble.
It will do everything under the
guidance of its own will, and nothing unexpected will befall it, but whatever
may be done by it will turn out well, and that, too, readily and easily,
without the doer having recourse to any underhand devices. For slow and
hesitating action are the signs of discord and want of settled purpose.
You may, then, boldly declare that the
highest good is singleness of mind: for where agreement and unity are, there also
must the virtues be. It is the vices that are at war one with another.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 8 (tr Stewart)
As a
child, I was often frightened and confused by how hectic, aggressive, and
confrontational the world was. I also began to see rather quickly how often
people liked to deceive, and that I would need some way to make sense of all
that smoke and mirrors.
In
kindergarten, one fellow dealt with it all by simply never speaking. Another
screamed and cried every day. A third learned to push first, and ask questions
later. I attempted something a little different. When I felt alone, uncertain,
or hurt by others, I would imagine my “home base”, those few dozen square feet
of space where I always felt safe. I usually visualized it as my small bedroom,
surrounded by my favorite toys and books, or the family parlor back in Austria,
surrounded by the people who comforted me. I saw it as that which was reliable,
what I could always return to after I struggled through everything out here
that was so unreliable.
The home
base grew from the image of a location to a state of mind, a way of thinking
about whatever felt threatening. However much I felt surrounded and blocked in,
I could still remember that there was that bit of me that couldn’t be hurt or
conquered. I recognized this instinct as a something Stoic only many years
later, by which time I had also learned that my own happiness or misery rose
and fell with how much or how little I depended on my unassailable home.
The home
base always had two constant features. First, I was in charge, and nothing
could enter that was not invited. Second, there was no place for discord or conflict
within its bounds. The whole moral physics, so to speak, of the place was
grounded in a love of unity and balance. Now while many people in the world
assured me there would have to be winners and losers in the war of achievement,
I knew I need not apply this to myself.
Just as
there can never be good relations between people who fight with one another, so
no man can be virtuous if he fights with himself. The virtuous man certainly
doesn’t need to isolate himself from the world, because as long as he has his
principles and his unity of purpose to guide him, he can throw himself into the
world unafraid. His impregnable fortress is never far, because he carries it
within himself.
19. Virtue
always as an end 1
"But," says our adversary,
"you yourself only practice virtue because you hope to obtain some
pleasure from it." In the first place, even though virtue may afford us
pleasure, still we do not seek after her on that account: for she does not
bestow this, but bestows this to boot, nor is this the end for which she
labors, but her labor wins this also, although it be directed to another end.
As in a tilled field, when ploughed for corn,
some flowers are found amongst it, and yet, though these posies may charm the
eye, all this labor was not spent in order to produce them—the man who sowed
the field had another object in view, he gained this over and above it—so
pleasure is not the reward or the cause of virtue, but comes in addition to it.
Nor do we choose virtue because she gives us pleasure, but she gives us
pleasure also if we choose her.
The highest good lies in the act of choosing
her, and in the attitude of the noblest minds, which when once it has fulfilled
its function and established itself within its own limits has attained to the
highest good, and needs nothing more. For there is nothing outside of the
whole, any more than there is anything beyond the end. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 9 (tr Stewart)
The
ancient Epicureans, or the modern Utilitarians, or the sensualists of any time
or place, might still insist that we desire virtue because we understand that
it leads to what is pleasurable. We can simply employ our reason, they claim,
to see that being a bad man is actually not very satisfying at all, and that
being a good man will give us the satisfaction we crave. By all means, the
argument goes, practice virtue, but in the knowledge of why we should practice
it.
Seneca
will still not budge in this matter, because I suspect he recognizes the
gravity of what is at stake. There can be no confusion as to whether good
actions or good feelings are the complete goal, and there can be no circularity
in stating that not all pleasures are desirable, while at the same time saying
actions are desirable precisely because they are pleasurable. The fundamental issue
is whether the highest good of human nature, toward which all other goods are
ordered, is defined by how we live, or by how we feel.
Remember
that the Stoic does not deny us pleasure, or ask that it be removed from our lives.
The Stoic will gladly embrace the reality that a good man can fell pleasure
through his virtue, and that such pleasure can be of the most wonderful and the
most beautiful sort. What matters is not only what we do and what we feel, but
why we do what we do, and how our actions and passions are rightly related.
I often
think not only of whether I should help my neighbor, but also of why I should
help my neighbor, and toward what end my deeds are ordered. Perhaps I want my
neighbor’s gratitude, or a favor in return down the line, or the respect of the
community, or maybe just that warm and fuzzy feeling that comes from having
made a difference. I may or may not receive such benefits, but as soon as I
have any of them in mind as my purpose, I haven’t really helped my neighbor at
all, but done something for the sake of my own passions. The giving became a
means to the receiving, and in this sense the giving became entirely
accidental.
Virtue
is only virtuous when it is for its own sake, just as love is only love for the
sake of the beloved. Once I have passed the good on, so to speak, to something
beyond itself, I have compromised and relativized both virtue and love.
Is the
farmer right to enjoy the beauty of wild flowers in his cultivated field? Yes, but
that is not why he should have cultivated the field. Is the worker right to
enjoy praise and promotion for his efforts? Yes, but that is not why he should
have worked hard. Is any man right to feel pleasure for having done the right
thing? Yes, but that is not why he should have done the right thing. The
pleasure is not the end itself, but something that can accompany the end. My
own variation of Seneca’s lesson is that I should gladly enjoy a good life, but
it hardly became good because I enjoyed it.
My own
experience has taught me that I will sometimes initially feel a certain pain
when I have followed my conscience, but that such pain will usually be replaced
by rather unexpected pleasures when I can think through why anything I did
really mattered. A worry about the things outside of my power gives way to an
appreciation for the things within my power.
Yet as
soon as I treat feeling itself as a cause of what is good in life, or as the
end of what is good in life, I have thrown away any and all of the benefits. By
deliberately seeking only an incomplete good, I have lost all of what is good.
20.
Virtue always as an end 2
. . . You are mistaken, therefore, when
you ask me what it is on account of which I seek after virtue, for you are
seeking for something above the highest. Do you ask what I seek from virtue? I
answer, herself, for she has nothing better. She is her own reward.
Does this not appear great enough, when
I tell you that the highest good is an unyielding strength of mind, wisdom,
magnanimity, sound judgment, freedom, harmony, beauty? Do you still ask me for
something greater, of which these may be regarded as the attributes?
Why do you talk of pleasures to me? I
am seeking to find what is good for man, not for his belly; why, cattle and
whales have larger bellies than he.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 9 (tr Stewart)
A wise
woman I once knew liked to say, “we speak as if we were angels, but we live as
if we were cattle.” We are sadly quite ready to make sweeping and noble claims
of virtue in public, while at the same time pursuing base pleasures in private.
We can only embrace what Seneca means here if we overcome that hypocritical
temptation. Loving virtue for its own sake can’t just be expressed as a grand
theory, but it must be lived as a daily practice.
This may
seem inconceivable to many of us, but we can fully understand this from both
ends, so to speak, from the cause, and from the consequence.
From the
cause, consider simply what it means to be human. That same wise woman also
told me there was a reason my head was at the top, and my guts were on the
bottom. My nature isn’t merely to consume what is pleasant, but to live with an
understanding of what is right and good. A human being only acts like a human
being, and therefore is only fully himself, when everything he does is ordered
by the knowledge of the truth and the love of the good.
From the
consequence, consider the profound benefits of living this way. Nothing can be
more stable, more serene, or more free than relying entirely upon the merits of
my own thoughts, decisions, and actions. If I rely upon my virtue, which is
completely within my own power, and no other conditions beyond it, I am truly
my own master. Everything I desire is already mine, and nothing else can add or
take from such harmony.
We may
be baffled by such a practice, even as we mouth the words, because we are
topsy-turvy, with our minds enslaved to our guts, and to the want of everything
outside of us. It is only our flawed estimation, and the years of poor examples
and bad habits, that keep us from genuine happiness.
I have
always had a great love of all animals, as my family will confirm with
exasperation, but as much as I admire a cow, or a whale, I will hardly respect
a man for the size of his stomach.
21. Pleasure
without honor
"You purposely misunderstand what
I say," he says, "for I too say that no one can live pleasantly
unless he lives honorably also, and this cannot be the case with dumb animals
who measure the extent of their happiness by that of their food. I loudly and
publicly proclaim that what I call a pleasant life cannot exist without the
addition of virtue."
Yet who does not know that the greatest
fools drink the deepest of those pleasures of yours? Or that vice is full of
enjoyments, and that the mind itself suggests to itself many perverted, vicious
forms of pleasure?
In the first place arrogance, excessive
self-esteem, swaggering precedence over other men, a shortsighted, no, a blind
devotion to his own interests, dissolute luxury, excessive delight springing
from the most trifling and childish causes.
Also talkativeness, pride that takes a
pleasure in insulting others, sloth, and the decay of a dull mind which goes to
sleep over itself. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 10 (tr Stewart)
The
sensualist may hope that he can have it both ways, and that he can live for
pleasure while at the same time being decent. He may even insist, as does
Seneca’s adversary, that the only pleasant life would of necessity also have to
be a virtuous one.
I can
understand such a temptation immediately, because it removes so many of the
apparent troubles I face in being happy, especially the perception of
conflicting standards. If I am to pursue pleasure, I will also find myself
being a good person at the same time.
Centuries
later, John Stuart Mill offered a similar argument. Pleasures, he said, should
be judged by their quality, and not merely by their quantity. Hence the
greatest pleasures will be those that fulfill the higher functions of man, and we
will find that true satisfaction proceeds from being thoughtful, refined, and
considerate. This is the context of his famous quote, "It
is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.”
At the level of theory,
this would hardly make pleasure the highest good anymore, because pleasure is
in turn measured and determined by the greater standard of wisdom and virtue.
Seneca will return to this aspect of his argument shortly.
For the moment, and at the
level of practice, it is surely sufficient to point out that a life of
satisfaction will hardly have to be a decent one. Look out into the world,
observe your neighbor, read the news, and you will promptly see that pleasure
seekers are usually not honorable and decent people at all. Even when the
sensualist is intelligent in his pursuit of satisfaction, he simply discovers
more clever ways to gratify himself.
I see
all the inhumanity around me, and I realize that what most of it has in common
is the pursuit of what feels good at the expense of doing good. Arrogance,
greed, lust, gluttony, laziness, anger, jealousy, or violence will all proceed
when I put my pleasure first, and consider other people simply as a means for
my pleasure. If I am to estimate everything through my passions, I choose to
close myself off to everything except those passions. If I make my reason
subservient to my feelings, my mind will not see things are they truly are, but
as I wish them to be.
I think
of all the times someone has done me wrong, and all the times I have done
someone else wrong, and it is a rejection of the good of the person for the
fulfillment of my own desire that usually binds them together.
I may
put lipstick on a pig. I may add all the appearances of culture, refinement,
good manners, and sophisticated tastes, but there is no way to elevate selfish
lust. It is vain, arrogant, and thoughtless by its very nature, because it
makes the world revolve around my feelings.
22.
Measure the value of pleasure
. . . All
these vices are dissipated by virtue, which plucks a man by the ear, and
measures the value of pleasures before she permits them to be used; nor does
she set much store by those which she allows to pass through, for she merely
allows their use, and her cheerfulness is not due to her use of them, but to
her moderation in using them.
"Yet when moderation lessens
pleasure, it impairs the highest good."
You devote yourself to pleasures, I
check them; you indulge in pleasure, I use it; you think that it is the highest
good, I do not even think it to be good: for the sake of pleasure I do nothing,
you do everything.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 10 (tr Stewart)
When
considered as the measure of happiness, pleasure itself will lead us only into
the pursuit of selfish desire. Even if I have acted with the appearance of
justice in order to increase my own power, or acted with the appearance of
courage in order to bolster my reputation, or acted with the appearance of
temperance at one moment for the sake greater satisfaction at another, I have
still reduced right and wrong to the whims of my passions.
Nature
does not revolve around how I feel, and I must consider my feelings by how my
choices and deeds exist within the harmony of the whole. Virtue, action ordered
by the knowledge of what is good and bad in things themselves, is the great
arbiter and mediator, the guide that shows me how I should relate to all of the
circumstances that accompany me in my life.
Sometimes
the world may give me wealth, and sometimes it may give me poverty. Sometimes
others will love me, and sometimes I will be despised. Perhaps most
importantly, sometimes I will feel pleasure, and sometimes I will feel pain.
I must
not take any of these things as good or bad in and of themselves, but I must
rather ask myself how I should make use of them, and how I should manage and
direct them, in order to live well. That is the measure of wisdom and virtue,
the greatest good within my own nature, that informs me about what I should
seek and what I should avoid.
I once
gave up the offer of a much more pleasant job because I had already signed
another contract, and later I once weaseled my way out of a different job
because of the lure of a much better one. The first choice was less convenient,
but it was the right one. The second choice was very convenient, but it was the
wrong one. Everything will bring with it different degrees of pleasure and
pain, but the only path to peace and contentment is resting in the knowledge
that, whatever the circumstances, I have treated both others and myself with
right respect. I still don’t regret the first decision at all, though I regret
the second one all of the time.
Not all
of my decisions will be useful or pleasant to my position in the world, but
they should always be beneficial to the content of my character. This is what I
owe to myself, and this is what I owe to others.
My own
attempts at the practice of Stoicism have only gradually come to a point where
I no longer look first to pleasure, wealth, power, or reputation as the
standards by which I think, decide, or act. I no longer seek to pursue pleasure
without condition, or to avoid pain without condition.
I seek
to measure the value of pleasure and pain, to filter their effect upon me,
through the constant of virtue. I should hardly be surprised anymore when a
change in the quality of my estimation leads to real change in the quality of
my living.
23. The
Master becomes the slave
When I say that I do nothing for the
sake of pleasure, I allude to that wise man, whom alone you admit to be capable
of pleasure.
Now I do not call a man wise who is
overcome by anything, let alone by pleasure. Yet, if engrossed by pleasure, how
will he resist toil, danger, want, and all the ills that surround and threaten
the life of man? How will he bear the sight of death or of pain? How will he
endure the tumult of the world, and make head against so many most active foes,
if he is conquered by so weak an antagonist?
He will do whatever pleasure advises
him. Well, do you not see how many things it will advise him to do?
"It will not," says our
adversary, "be able to give him any bad advice, because it is combined
with virtue."
Again, do you not see what a poor kind
of highest good that must be which requires a guardian to ensure its being good
at all? And how is virtue to rule pleasure if she follows it, seeing that to
follow is the duty of a subordinate, to rule that of a commander? Do you put that
which commands in the background? . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 11 (tr Stewart)
Whenever
I have sought after pleasure, I have thought of myself as a powerful conqueror,
and if I only tried hard enough, the world was there for the taking. There is
indeed a certain feeling of achievement in getting what I want. This is an
illusion. I am not getting what I want, but what I want is getting me.
The sensualist
may be clever, cunning, and forceful in pursuing his goal, but he is not
pulling the strings. He does not rule himself at all, but rather is ruled by
his passions, and he is pushed and pulled by the external objects of his
desires.
I think
of all those images from literature and film where the mighty hunter realizes
that he has become the hunted. That wonderful scene from Jurassic Park, when Muldoon succumbs to the raptors, comes to mind
whenever I have sadly let myself be fooled: “Clever girl!” Admiral Ackbar from Return of the Jedi is not far behind:
“It’s a trap!”
If a man
allows himself to be determined by pleasure and pain, or by any of the
circumstances of his life, he is hardly strong at all, but is actually quite
weak. Change the condition, and you change him. Give him something from the
outside, and he feels happy; take it away, and he is miserable. He laughs or
cries depending on the direction of the wind.
But
surely if my want for pleasure is accompanied by virtue, says the Epicurean, I
will make good choices. The mouse will not fall for the cheese if he knows
what’s good for him.
There’s
the rub. As soon as I say that pleasure must be tempered by virtue, or that my
desires must always be directed by wisdom, pleasure is no longer the highest
good at all. Its value is now relative, because it depends upon another measure.
The sensualist, while still insisting that happiness is pleasure, is beginning
to sound more and more like a Stoic.
24. Ill
at ease
. . . According
to your school, virtue has the dignified office of preliminary tester of
pleasures. We shall, however, see whether virtue still remains virtue among
those who treat her with such contempt, for if she leaves her proper station
she can no longer keep her proper name.
In the meanwhile, to keep to the point,
I will show you many men beset by pleasures, men upon whom Fortune has showered
all her gifts, whom you must admit to be bad men.
Look at Nomentanus and Apicius, who
digest all the good things, as they call them, of the sea and land, and review
upon their tables the whole animal kingdom. Look at them as they lie on beds of
roses gloating over their banquet, delighting their ears with music, their eyes
with exhibitions, their palates with flavors. Their whole bodies are titillated
with soft and soothing applications, and lest even their nostrils should be
idle, the very place in which they solemnize the rites of luxury is scented
with various perfumes.
You will say that these men live in the
midst of pleasures. Yet they are ill at ease, because they take pleasure in
what is not good.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 11 (tr Stewart)
The
problem here boils down to whether virtue is to serve our appetites, or if our
appetites are to serve virtue. If the standards of right and wrong depend upon
desire, however, one will hardly have any right or wrong at all. Morality will
shift and change based upon the convenience of our feelings, and we can clearly
discern the root of the moral relativism that we see all around us.
I was
once speaking to a fellow who insisted that cheating on his wife was actually
doing her a favor. I wasn’t at all sure what to say when he explained that his
trysts, which were only occasional, mind you, as if that made them any better,
helped him to be more calm and relaxed, and that this made her life easier.
There you have the sort of man whose conscience is in the service of his
passions.
Seeing
how the pleasure seeker lives has long saddened me, and I am also deeply
ashamed whenever I have lived this way. The objects of desire may be sex, food,
drink, luxury, money, reputation, or power, but regardless of what it is that
may gratify us, we inevitably become selfish, manipulative, entitled, dishonest,
and disloyal. In desiring to possess and consume, in serving myself, it becomes
impossible for me to serve. Life becomes about grasping, not about giving.
Nomentanus
and Apicius were apparently Roman gourmets, perhaps gourmands, perhaps most
accurately gluttons, well known for their elaborate and luxurious tastes. We
like to frown upon the decadence of the past, though we are hardly any better. I
have had two moments of epiphany about our own excesses, both of which are indelibly
burned into my memory.
The
first was one of those rare moments when I found myself in the world of other
half, in a fancy corporate office on one of the top floors of a skyscraper in
Boston’s Financial District. The cost of the marble and fittings in the
restrooms surely cost more than I would ever earn in my entire lifetime, and
the catered food was worth more than at least a year of my own grocery budget.
I was in awe, but the important people took it all for granted, and one griped
that the champagne was far below his standards.
The
second was just a normal shopping trip with my wife, and we came across a
mother and her two children. The woman was speaking loudly on her cell phone,
complaining to someone about her manicurist. An obese boy sat in in the
shopping cart, wolfing down handfuls of chips from a large bag, leaving a trail
of crumbs behind him on the floor. A slightly older girl, perhaps eleven or
twelve, wearing tight lycra stamped with the word “juicy” on her bottom, was
singing along to Miley Cyrus on her iPod.
I don’t
wish to think of the world as being full of such mindless gorging, not so
different from animals feeding at the trough, but such experiences make it
difficult not to lose hope. I must think not of the symptoms, but of the cure,
and I must remember that the solution is never to simply complain about others,
whether it is about champagne, or manicures, or even gluttonous practices, but
to improve myself.
The
reason I am ill at ease, as Seneca says, when I pursue pleasure as an end is
that I am trying to fill myself with things that are not really part of my
nature at all. I am made to understand, not to conform. I am made to do good
things, not to consume them. I am made to love, not to be gratified.
25. A
merry madness
"They are ill at ease," he
replies, "because many things arise which distract their thoughts, and
their minds are disquieted by conflicting opinions."
I admit that this is true. Still, these
very men, foolish, inconsistent, and certain to feel remorse as they are, do
nevertheless receive great pleasure, and we must allow that in so doing they
are as far from feeling any trouble as they are from forming a right judgment,
and that, as is the case with many people, they are possessed by a merry
madness, and laugh while they rave.
The pleasures of wise men, on the other
hand, are mild, decorous, verging on dullness, kept under restraint and
scarcely noticeable, and are neither invited to come nor received with honor
when they come of their own accord, nor are they welcomed with any delight by
those whom they visit, who mix them up with their lives and fill up empty
spaces with them, like an amusing farce in the intervals of serious business. .
. .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 12 (tr Stewart)
Seneca’s
adversary suggests that the pleasure seeker may be ill at ease simply because he
is sometimes distracted or confused. Seneca
agrees, though he considers that the confusion is much deeper, and arises
precisely because people have chosen to pursue a completely misguided end,
which in turn arises from completely misguided judgment.
If I had
read this passage as a much younger man, I would probably have scoffed at
Seneca’s colorful distinction between those who seek pleasure and those who
seek virtue. I might even have said that I would prefer to be the crazed
buffoon than the uptight stick-in-the-mud, because at the very least the raving
pleasure seeker might get a bit of fun out of the whole thing.
Seneca
never minces his words, of course, which hardly makes him a writer who will
appeal to the young and brash. With all the extreme images aside, experience
has come to teach me precisely what he means.
I have
now seen it all too often. Drunks sit in the bar, pretending to enjoy a happy
hour, their faces devoid of any reflection or contentment. Junkies grasp violently
at anything and everything as they come off of their high. Philanderers drive
themselves insane in the pursuit of their prey. The captains of industry are
obsessed with increasing their assets. The politicians struggle to be more
liked. The proper professionals run around wildly in the hopes of improving
their power and position. It happens in every walk of life, and it is indeed a
form of madness. We ignore our better judgment in favor of gratification,
though if we are given all the pleasures we seek, we are still ill at ease.
In contrast,
the wise man, the man who pursues virtue as his end, will certainly appear to
be bland, cold and unfeeling. He will certainly appear this way to the
sensualist. I imagine that, seen from the outside in, this is why Stoicism is
considered a philosophy without any emotion.
I must
always remember, however, that the Stoic does not reject pleasure. He will
receive it, he will enjoy it with calm and with moderation, but he will not
make it his purpose or pursue it for its own sake. It is an addition to the
value of his living, not the measure of his living. He will seem dull and
boring because he is at peace with what is within himself, never frantic for
acquiring what is outside of himself.
The wise
man will hardly care if he is found amusing or interesting, and certainly not
by the sort of people who follow a slavishness to externals. He will be happy
to be himself, in the peace of his own nature, and he will immediately
recognize and welcome any who are one the same path.
Happiness
is not a frenzied rat race, not the struggle to gain more and more. It is the
peace of living well, with however much or little Fortune may have given us.
26. A
cloak for vices
. . . Let them no longer, then, join
incongruous matters together, or connect pleasure with virtue, a mistake
whereby they court the worst of men. The reckless profligate, always in liquor
and belching out the fumes of wine, believes that he lives with virtue, because
he knows that he lives with pleasure, for he hears it said that pleasure cannot
exist apart from virtue.
Consequently he dubs his vices with the
title of wisdom and parades all that he ought to conceal. So, men are not
encouraged by Epicurus to run riot, but the vicious hide their excesses in the
lap of philosophy, and flock to the schools in which they hear the praises of
pleasure. They do not consider how sober and temperate —for so, by Hercules, I
believe it to be—that "pleasure" of Epicurus is, but they rush at his
mere name, seeking to obtain some protection and cloak for their vices.
They lose, therefore, the one virtue
which their evil life possessed, that of being ashamed of doing wrong: for they
praise what they used to blush at, and boast of their vices. Thus modesty can
never reassert itself, when shameful idleness is dignified with an honorable
name. The reason why that praise which your school lavishes upon pleasure is so
hurtful, is because the honorable part of its teaching passes unnoticed, but
the degrading part is seen by all.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 12 (tr Stewart)
Seneca
speaks his mind without hesitation, but he is not a close-minded or dismissive
philosopher. He still disagrees in principle with the Epicurean theory that
happiness is defined by pleasure, but he is also willing to see that Epicurus
himself also preached temperance and moderation, and that the greater problem
is how others misrepresent and abuse the Epicurean teachings.
It will
hardly help us to distinguish right from wrong, without also trying to
understand why people choose right
from wrong. Seneca considers the sensualists, and he thinks he sees one of the
ways their thinking has gone astray.
Perhaps
I have been told all of my life that I must somehow be “good”, even if I’ve
only been given some vague directions to behave myself and stay out of trouble,
while at the same time I’ve been warned that I must not simply do things
because they fulfill my appetites.
But now
imagine that a philosopher comes along who tells me that virtue is really just
whatever can give me the greatest pleasure. It hardly matters that Epicurus
also told us to be moderate in our pleasures in order to be happy, because the
teaching on the primacy of my appetites now seems to give me the excuse to do
whatever I want. I take that first bit, and ignore all the rest.
Before I
heard of this new philosophy, I might at least have felt ashamed of my vices,
but now I revel in them. I believe I have been liberated from all the old
restrictions by the illusion that something must be good only because I desire
it. Epicurus may never have intended it, but a corruption of his philosophy has
had the effect of making bad men even worse. Whatever there still was of a
conscience to provide restraint, however unformed, has now been completely
excised.
There
have been many times in my life where I’ve been drawn to various forms of
sensualism and relativism, usually under the counter-culture umbrella of “If it
feels good, do it.” I’ve felt the pressure of uptight moralists many times, the
ones who are all just about a heartless conformity to the rules, and I have
felt smothered.
Yet I
must be careful not to throw the baby out with the bathwater. There must be
freedom and joy in life, but that cannot be at the cost of my sense of
responsibility and respect, or by making virtue a cloak for my vices. Things
don’t become good because I desire them, but I should rather desire them
because they are good, and this is why wisdom and virtue should rule over
passion and pleasure. Love is never the same thing as lust.
27. Epicurus
and the Stoic comrades
I myself believe, though my Stoic
comrades would be unwilling to hear me say so, that the teaching of Epicurus
was upright and holy, and even, if you examine it narrowly, strong: for this
much talked of pleasure is reduced to a very narrow compass, and he bids
pleasure submit to the same law which we bid virtue do—I mean, to obey Nature.
Luxury, however, is not satisfied with
what is enough for nature. What is the consequence? Whoever thinks that
happiness consists in lazy sloth, and alternations of gluttony and profligacy,
requires a good patron for a bad action, and when he has become an Epicurean,
having been led to do so by the attractive name of that school, he follows, not
the pleasure which he there hears spoken of, but that which he brought there with
him, and, having learned to think that his vices coincide with the maxims of
that philosophy, he indulges in them no longer timidly and in dark corners, but
boldly in the face of day.
I will not, therefore, like most of our
school, say that the sect of Epicurus is the teacher of crime, but what I say
is: it is ill spoken of, it has a bad reputation, and yet it does not deserve
it. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 13 (tr Stewart)
I have
never had much patience for any philosophy that is dogmatic and exclusive, since
the truth should be acquired through reasoning, not by authority, and it should
be something shared, not something fractured. This should apply especially to
Stoicism, ordered as it is toward the harmony of all things, and not toward
conflict.
I
learned to deeply respect the philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas precisely
because he was a thinker who was always willing and able to see the different
senses of meaning, and would always strive to point out what was common before
he explained a disagreement. I was always saddened by the sort of Thomists who
completely missed this point.
A
respect for others means that we can begin with what is shared, and then use
our own errors as a means to improvement. Seneca knows that there will be some
Stoics, perhaps more interested in the name than the task, who prefer to
condemn instead of understand. Seneca, however, is willing to give credit where
credit is due.
Epicurus
did indeed hold pleasure to be the highest good, but his conviction was that
such pleasure must always be calm and moderate, and should obey Nature. If this
is indeed the case, Seneca argues that passion must therefore actually follow reason and virtue, because any
pleasure is qualified and conditioned by whether it is understood to be good or
bad. Epicurus may have gotten the order of priority wrong in his thinking, but
he modeled a very similar way of living in his practice.
This, of
course, isn’t true of many of his followers, then and now, who would have
reason and virtue as slaves to unbridled desire. To be fair, such a
misunderstanding might be similar to that of an extreme Stoic who thinks that
virtue is just toughness, or that possessions are evil, or that pleasure should
be repressed.
I have
always hoped to discover something bigger than myself in a philosophy, and not
just impose my own preferences upon it.
28. What
better guide?
. . . "Who can know this without
having been admitted to its inner mysteries?" Its very outside gives
opportunity for scandal, and encourages men's baser desires. It is like a brave
man dressed in a woman's gown: your chastity is assured, your manhood is safe,
your body is submitted to nothing disgraceful, but your hand holds a drum, like
a priest of Cybele.
Choose, then, some honorable
superscription for your school, some writing which shall in itself arouses the
mind. That which at present stands over your door has been invented by the
vices. He who ranges himself on the side of virtue gives thereby a proof of a
noble disposition. He who follows pleasure appears to be weakly, worn out,
degrading his manhood, likely to fall into infamous vices unless someone
discriminates his pleasures for him, so that he may know which remain within
the bounds of natural desire, which are frantic and boundless, and become all
the more insatiable the more they are satisfied.
But come! Let virtue lead the way! Then
every step will be safe. Too much pleasure is hurtful, but with virtue we need
fear no excess of any kind, because moderation is contained in virtue herself.
That which is injured by its own extent cannot be a good thing: besides, what
better guide can there be than reason for beings endowed with a reasoning nature?
So if this combination pleases you, if
you are willing to proceed to a happy life thus accompanied, let virtue lead
the way, let pleasure follow and hang about the body like a shadow. It is the
part of a mind incapable of great things to hand over virtue, the highest of
all qualities, as a handmaid to pleasure.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 13 (tr Stewart)
Even if
the Epicureans had some hidden doctrines that might explain more about their
teachings, a trait that was common to many Greek and Roman schools, Seneca insists
that the outward appearance itself has already done the harm. It has been the
draw of pleasure alone that has attracted followers. It will make little
difference if some virtue on the inside is cloaked in a vice on the outside.
The
analogy of the Galli, the eunuch
priests of Cybele, refers to men who appeared in public like women. This reference
may seem insensitive to our current cultural norms about gender, but a Roman
reader would surely have seen that Seneca was pointing to the contrast between
the external and the internal.
Seneca
summarizes his entire core argument nicely here. Happiness must be something
good in itself, and nothing good in itself would ever do us harm. But pleasure
can do us great harm, and it can therefore never be the end of happiness. Only
moderation can give balance and meaning to our pleasures, and moderation, in
turn, is a part of virtue.
How can we
come to this virtue? It is through the exercise of reason, which can perceive
what is good by understanding the very nature of things themselves. Reason is
the guide, and the passions should follow. Each is a necessary aspect of who we
are, but they are aspects in a proper order.
The very
fact that we are able to reflect upon the meaning of our existence, the nature
of the good life, or the path to happiness is an immediate indication of our distinct
human nature. I am a being with a body, with instincts and feelings, acting and
being acted upon by the world around me. Yet what remains constant and at the
core of that human experience is the power to think and to decide, to not
merely be moved by other things, but to move my own actions through awareness.
We live
in a very appetitive age, with so much of our attention directed at feelings
and images. These are indeed part of our existence, but they are hardly the
whole, and they are hardly the most vital part. A feeling must be measured by
right to be good, and an image must be judged by truth to be understood.
This is
the role of virtue, of excellence in action, which is the fulfillment of a
being with a rational nature. It highlights the critical difference between a
man who defines himself by how good he feels, and a man who defines himself by
how well he acts.
29. Let
virtue lead the way.
Let virtue lead the way and bear the
standard. We shall have pleasure for all that, but we shall be her masters and
controllers; she may win some concessions from us, but she will not force us to
do anything.
On the contrary, those who have
permitted pleasure to take the lead will have neither one nor the other.
For they lose virtue altogether, and
yet they do not possess pleasure, but are possessed by it, and are either
tortured by its absence or choked by its excess, being wretched if deserted by
it, and yet more wretched if overwhelmed by it, like those who are caught in
the shoals
of the Syrtes and at one time are left on dry ground and at another tossed on
the flowing waves.
This arises from an exaggerated want of
self-control, and a hidden love of evil. For it is dangerous for one who seeks
after evil instead of good to attain his object. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 14 (tr Stewart)
I often worry
that too much of my life was wasted on wanting things that felt good, instead of being dedicated to doing things that are good. When I was a young fellow, I
wanted to be loved. There were no takers. At that time in my life, where the
only measure of right and wrong was how accepted I was, I felt horribly alone.
One day,
at a party at an old friend’s house, I ended up sitting next to a girl I had met
a few times before. I had certainly admired her from afar. She was quite attractive,
and also incredibly bright. She suddenly licked my nose, and grinned at me.
Now what’s
a fellow to do? I know what most men would say, but I am not an example of most
men. I kissed her, I walked her home, and then I asked her out for a date at her
door.
She
laughed at me, but I told her that I meant what I had said. That was the beginning
of my own grief. I was trying to be a gentleman, but my motives were still
rooted in desire. The fault was never hers, because she was already who she
was. The fault was mine, because I didn’t know who I was.
I
allowed my desire to do my thinking for me. The next day, I found out that she
had already been seeing a friend of mine. No worries, I thought, I will treat
her better, and I will earn her love.
The next
week, it was the University Chorale trip, and she came back bragging about the
two fellows she’d played around with. I had no clue how to respond to that, but
I tried to explain that I thought our relationship was between us, and that there
would be no other playing.
A month later,
she finally told me about her long-term boyfriend in New Zealand. I said it was
either about him or about me, and she apparently chose me. I thought at the
time it was about love, but I now know it was about my own selfishness.
Now any decent
man, anyone in his right mind, would have immediately seen what was happening,
and would have run to the hills. I was not thinking, however, but rather only
feeling. I was not choosing, but rather only desiring. My gut had gotten a hold
of my head. I did not possess what I desired, but my desires possessed me, and
I had thrown out my own character in the bargain.
Over many
years, I thought she had become my best friend, and I could not imagine my life
without her. Yet I still recall the time I found her at a party, drunkenly wrapped
around a fellow on a couch, and I still recall the time I wanted to propose marriage
to her, but she didn’t answer the door, because she had another one of my
friends in her bed.
Most men
would blame her. I finally learned only to blame myself. I allowed my pleasure
to rule me, because I never chose to make my virtue rule my pleasure. I longed
for something through my passions, but getting what I wanted never satisfied me.
There was never any happiness in all of the longing. I was constantly moved
between being tortured by absence and choking on excess.
There is
no such thing as winning or possessing another person. There is only loving
another person. My own lack of self-control was the root of my own misery, and I
ended up proving that Seneca was quite right. He who lets his virtue be ruled
by his pleasure loses both his virtue and his pleasure.
30. Taming
wild beasts
. . . As we hunt wild beasts with toil
and peril, and even when they are caught find them an anxious possession, for
they often tear their keepers to pieces, even so are great pleasures. They turn
out to be great evils and take their owners prisoner. The more numerous and the
greater they are, the more inferior and the slave of more masters does that man
become whom the vulgar call a happy man.
I may even press this analogy further:
as the man who tracks wild animals to their lairs, and who sets great store on
"seeking with snares the wandering brutes to noose," and "making
their hounds the spacious glade surround," that he may follow their
tracks, neglects far more desirable things, and leaves many duties unfulfilled,
so he who pursues pleasure postpones everything to it, disregards that first
essential, liberty, and sacrifices it to his belly; nor does he buy pleasure
for himself, but sells himself to pleasure.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 14 (tr Stewart)
I
remember a news story back in the 1980’s, though I hardly know where the facts
ended and the urban legend began, about a yuppie family in Colorado that
decided to adopt a wolf cub. They apparently saw themselves as being very
progressive, and spoke proudly about participating in the harmony of nature.
The only
problem was, that as that wolf cub grew older, he behaved exactly as any wolf
would. One evening, the husband was trying to romance his wife, and the wolf
attacked him. All the Windham Hill music and fancy California wines would not
tame the wolf, because he was challenging the alpha male of the pack for
breeding rights. You can take the wolf out of nature, but you can’t take nature
out of the wolf.
Even the
most domesticated animal is rarely “tamed”. My wife and I still have scars on
our legs from an attack by one of our cats, who suddenly felt that we were
threatening one of our other kittens. Her maternal protective instincts kicked
in for some reason, and I can still vividly recall the feeling of warm blood pouring
down my leg after she had done her business.
A man
can certainly be a part of Nature, but he will never conquer it. Nature is not
about fairies and buttercups. There will be loss, there will be pain, and there
will be death. All of this is a part of how things should rightly be, and each
aspect of the fullness of Nature plays its own distinct role. The role of man
is to understand himself, to rule himself by his own character, and to die
knowing that he has done right.
Now why
should I hunt and pursue other things? I speak not of the entitled or the
barbaric, some of whom believe that simply killing a wild animal somehow makes
them better. I’m speaking about all of us, who are told and tempted to make
ourselves better by conquest and consumption.
Pleasure
is a fickle prey. I may seek my pleasure where I will, in sex, in alcohol or
drugs, in power, or in my reputation. I am not immune because or my background
or class. The beast I am after, the one I wish to tame, is actually after me,
and it will end up dominating me.
How much
of my time and effort have I dedicated to hunting for gratification, for
possessions, for position? In turn, how much have I consequently neglected the
nurturing of my own soul? Why do I permit myself to be ruled by a desire for
the things outside of me, when my complete good is to be found inside of me? As
Howard Jones, one of my old musical heroes, said: “Hunt the Self.”
31. That
proverbial cake
"But what," asks our
adversary, "is there to hinder virtue and pleasure being combined
together, and a highest good being thus formed, so that honor and pleasure may
be the same thing?"
Because nothing except what is
honorable can form a part of honor, and the highest good would lose its purity
if it were to see within itself anything unlike its own better part.
Even the joy which arises from virtue,
although it is a good thing, yet is not a part of absolute good, any more than
cheerfulness or peace of mind, which are indeed good things, but which merely
follow the highest good, and do not contribute to its perfection, although they
are generated by the noblest causes. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 15 (tr Stewart)
There
are few things more tempting, and few things we will dedicate ourselves to more
desperately and frantically, than trying to have it both ways. Being told that we
can’t have our cake and eat it too seems to make us uncomfortable and squirmy.
I have heard dozens of ridiculous semantic contortions that vainly try to
explain away the logical principle of non-contradiction, and thereby insist that
my cake can be both on my plate and in my belly at the same time.
I
suspect that sometimes we know quite well that we cannot have or be two
conflicting things, but we may desire the reality of one of them and merely the
appearance of the other. I know that this is what I have meant when I think I
can give equal value to both virtue and pleasure. Give me the gratification, but
make it look like I’m being noble in getting it.
I cannot
treat virtue and pleasure as being equally good, or as always being in agreement
with one another, or as one and the same thing. Virtue, by its very definition
as the excellence of our actions, is always unconditionally good, while
pleasure is only conditionally good, dependent upon the value of the action
from which it proceeds. I have never
gone wrong in my life by doing the right thing, but I have often gone wrong in
my life by craving the wrong thing. That which is superior cannot be measured
by what is inferior.
Living
well may indeed give me a feeling of approval, and I have often found that the
pleasure that can follows from a virtue is far more satisfying than the
pleasure that can follow from a vice. This seems quite fitting, because the
former is about our human fulfillment, while the latter is about our emptiness
through dependence.
Yet as
soon as I treat the pleasure as an end itself, and not merely as an associated
consequence, I have already cast aside that very act of moral fulfillment. I
cannot be doing the right thing for all the wrong reasons, or aim for what is
good in itself when all I really seek is what feels good to me.
There
are many other things in life that can be good, but as a consequence and not as
the cause. The relative always flows out from the absolute. I am not a good man
because I am cheerful, friendly, or mild-mannered, but I will certainly be
cheerful, friendly, and mild-mannered if I am a good man. I don’t become kind
if someone respects me, but I can be respected if I am kind. Being wealthy
won’t make me fair, but my fairness could make me wealthy.
In the
relationship of virtue and pleasure, one will have to lead, and the other will
have to follow. I often think of the passage from Matthew 6:24:
No
one can serve two masters; for either he will hate the one and love the other,
or he will be devoted to the one and despise the other. You cannot serve God
and mammon.
32. Liberty
under the yoke
. . . Whoever on the other hand forms
an alliance, and that, too, a one-sided one, between virtue and pleasure, clogs
whatever strength the one may possess by the weakness of the other, and sends
liberty under the yoke, for liberty can only remain unconquered as long as she
knows nothing more valuable than herself.
For he begins to need the help of Fortune,
which is the most utter slavery. His life becomes anxious, full of suspicion,
timorous, fearful of accidents, waiting in agony for critical moments of time.
You do not afford virtue a solid immovable base if you bid it stand on what is
unsteady, and what can be so unsteady as dependence on mere chance, and the
vicissitudes of the body and of those things that act on the body?
How can such a man obey God and receive
everything which comes to pass in a cheerful spirit, never complaining of fate,
and putting a good construction upon everything that befalls him, if he be
agitated by the petty pin-pricks of pleasures and pains?
A man cannot be a good protector of his
country, a good avenger of her wrongs, or a good defender of his friends, if he
is inclined to pleasures. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 15 (tr Stewart)
The
liberty Seneca speaks of is the power to rule oneself, that foundation upon
which the whole structure of Stoic happiness is built. To be genuinely free is
not to assert the power of the will over
the world, but to take complete responsibility for our choices in the world.
The
happy man should not expect to shape things in his own image, and Fortune will
have her own way with what is under her authority. The happy man will rather
improve himself regarding what is under his own authority, in the way that he
judges, chooses, and acts. To permit my own happiness to depend upon my
circumstances is to make those circumstances more valuable than myself, whether
it is in the pursuit of pleasure, or of fame, or of power. These things are not
mine, they do not concern me, and I enslave myself to them whenever I choose to
pursue them. My weakness is then in the willful surrender of my self-reliance.
If I
wish to build upon something unmoving, I need only look to Nature, and how she
asks me to live within her order. I often notice how our frustration and
complaints at the unfair ways of the world seem to become more exaggerated as
we become more spoiled and entitled. This should be a clear sign that the
things we think are gifts to our freedom are actually only burdens to our
happiness. I need to change the focus of my attention.
Growing
up in New England, I was baffled by the many luxurious vacation houses built on
beaches that would soon be washed away by the elements. When I moved west, I
noticed how greedy developers built family homes that soon succumbed to
flooding or plunged into sinkholes. There is then often outrage and blame, even
though people of common sense had known for centuries not to build on such poor
land.
As one
of my old philosophy professors, known for his especially painful sense of
humor, would often say, “The yokes on you.”
33. Rise
to that height . . .
. . . Let the highest good, then, rise
to that height from which no force can dislodge it, where no pain can ascend,
no hope, no fear, nor anything else that can impair the authority of the highest
good.
There alone virtue can make her way; by
her aid that hill must be climbed. She will bravely stand her ground and endure
whatever may befall her not only resignedly, but even willingly.
She will know that all hard times come
in obedience to natural laws, and like a good soldier, she will bear wounds,
count scars, and when transfixed and dying will yet adore the general for whom
she falls. She will bear in mind the old maxim, "Follow God." . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 15 (tr Stewart)
The
truly happy life will be one that is in a state of unassailable liberty. Like any
proper Roman, Seneca employs the image of a soldier capturing and holding the
high ground, though such a martial theme may not speak to everyone. One might
also consider the analogy of how the ascent of a mountain provides a broader
perspective, or how the undertaking of a journey builds awareness and
commitment, or how the safety of one’s true home can offer comfort and
stability from a painful world.
I once,
only partly in jest, made use of the story of The Three Little Pigs to
explain something similar to a group of fifth graders. They were young enough
to still know the story, but also old enough to start reflecting on all the
different things it could mean; they were at that wonderful point between the
grammar and dialectic stages of learning.
There
will be those things in the world that seem to threaten us, and those people in
the world who want to hurt us. That would be the Wolf.
We worry
about the dangers, and we wonder what barriers we can put between those dangers
and ourselves. Those would be the pigs and their houses.
If we rely
upon the weak and pliable defenses of Fortune, and we prepare ourselves poorly,
we will succumb to our circumstances. Those would be the first two pigs and
their houses made of straw and wood.
But if
we build upon something immovable, and we are ready for whatever may befall us,
we may count ourselves content in this life. That would be the last pig and his
house of stone.
This
perhaps reflects poorly upon me, but I always preferred the older versions of
the tale, the ones that hadn’t been cleaned up, where the wolf tries to come
down the chimney, is trapped in a pot of boiling hot water, and becomes lunch
for the pig. Not only is the last pig safe, but the tables have also been
turned.
Some
people think that rising above our conditions involves simply denying the
danger, ignoring what is real, or disposing of whatever burdens us. That is
hardly virtue, but cowardice.
Seneca’s
soldier fighting for the high ground is not running from the battle, but is in
the midst of the carnage. It is not that he is immune to pain and death, but
that he faces these things with character. He may fall in the battle, but it is
not his body that is invulnerable. It is his soul that cannot be defeated,
because he knows that his own virtue is that unconquerable highest good.
My
virtue is my house of stone, because no one can take it from me.
To
“follow God” is not the murderous ravings of the fanatic, who is driven by his
own hatred and desire to conquer others, or the despair of the determinist, who
has already surrendered to blind fate. For the Stoic, it means understanding
that all of Nature follows a Divine order and purpose, and that I can freely
choose to find my own peace within Nature by living well. This never depends upon
what happens to me, but upon what I do.
In my
own mind, I will often think about the squares of British infantry that stood
against the French cavalry at the Battle of Waterloo in 1815. It is hardly their
final victory in the battle itself that inspires me, because I have much the
same respect for the opposing French Cuirassiers.
Whatever
image can help us to understand this ideal, I believe it requires the
recognition that any true victory is over oneself, and not over another.
34. The
liberty to obey
. . . On the other hand, he who
grumbles and complains and bemoans himself is nevertheless forcibly obliged to
obey orders, and is dragged away, however much against his will, to carry them
out.
Yet what madness is it to be dragged
rather than to follow? As great, by Hercules, as it is folly and ignorance of
one's true position to grieve because one has not got something, or because something
has caused us rough treatment, or to be surprised or indignant at those ills
which befall good men as well as bad ones, I mean diseases, deaths, illnesses,
and the other cross accidents of human life.
Let us bear with magnanimity whatever
the system of the Universe makes it needful for us to bear. We are all bound by
this oath: "To bear the ills of mortal life, and to submit with a good grace
to what we cannot avoid."
We have been born into a monarchy: our
liberty is to obey God.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 15 (tr Stewart)
In our
supposedly democratic and egalitarian age, we dislike the very idea of obeying.
This is, I suspect, because we automatically assume that it proceeds only from
fear or coercion. We avoid speeding in our cars, so the conventional wisdom
goes, because we fear the sanction of receiving a ticket. We resent the
intrusion, but we submit begrudgingly. This is why we feel liberated by
breaking the law when no one is looking.
Like
good Utilitarians, we may show kindness to others because we fear the sanction
of social disapproval. We may not enjoy it, but we submit begrudgingly. This is
why we feel liberated by mocking or dismissing others when they are not
looking.
How many
times have I slammed on the brakes when I see a police car? How many times have
I found a sinister pleasure in gossiping about someone to whom I had just given
a friendly smile moments earlier?
It
doesn’t have to be that way. I can choose to drive safely, or show respect to
my neighbor, not because I have to, but because I want to. I need not obey out
of fear, but because I know that something is right. I can replace that
resentment with willing love.
Nature
will unfold according to her own laws, and things in this world will be as they
are, often far beyond my power to determine. What remains for me is to decide
how I will relate to everything that is around me. Will I freely join with
Nature, or will I oppose and resist her? Will I work with or against the good
in things? Will I take Fortune and all of my circumstances, whether painful or
pleasant, with character and dignity, or will I demand and complain? Either
way, I will be subject to Providence, but as a partner in one way, or as a prisoner
in another.
Over the
years, I had many students who resisted learning, who felt that they were merely
being forced to jump through all the hoops of education. In many ways they were
quite right, because so much of what we consider schooling has sadly become an
exercise in conformity and submission.
I
reminded them that the norms of our society, right or wrong, do indeed demand
this of them, but they may now make of this whatever they choose. Are they
willing to discover something in the situation, to freely decide to find
something valuable in what is before them? I suggested they think less about
bowing to their teachers, or running after the best grades, and simply become
curious for their own sake, and to think for themselves. It was funny how all
the grades and achievements took care of themselves, if only they made that
willing commitment.
For many
years, I have felt bound by the profound promises I made to my wife. Sometimes
it has been a joy, and sometimes it has been a struggle. There has been great
pleasure, and there has also been great pain, as there is in all walks of life.
That commitment holds meaning not because I must follow, but because I choose
to follow. I submit and obey not from a law of fear or force, but from a law of
hope and love. I am bound, for better or for worse, because I wish to be bound.
We may
not be too keen on the idea of monarchy these days, but when Seneca speaks of
God as a king, he means it not as a tyrant to be feared, but as a benefactor to
be loved.
35. Defining
bad or good
True happiness, therefore, consists in
virtue. And what will this virtue bid you to do? Not to think of anything as
bad or good which is connected neither with virtue nor with wickedness. And in
the next place, both to endure unmoved the assaults of evil, and, as far as is
right, to form a god out of what is good.
What reward does she promise you for
this campaign? An enormous one, and one that raises you to the level of the
gods. You shall be subject to no restraint and to no want; you shall be free,
safe, unhurt; you shall fail in nothing that you attempt; you shall be debarred
from nothing; everything shall turn out according to your wish; no misfortune
shall befall you; nothing shall happen to you except what you expect and hope
for. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 16 (tr Stewart)
We
constantly label things in our lives as “good” or “bad”. That promotion at the
firm, the one that comes with a bigger salary, more vacation days, and the
window office, is surely something good, or at least that’s what they told me
back in Boston. The fact that my truck broke down, my dog died, and my girl
left me is surely something bad, or at least that’s what they tell me in
Oklahoma.
Yet it
has been precisely that sort of thinking that has made me miserable. It reduces
to the scramble to acquire and avoid what is outside of us. That every thing in
Nature, each with its own identity and purpose, is good in its own being is
hopefully clear enough, but that things are as they are is neither here nor
there when it comes to my own happiness. What is good or bad, as specific to my
own human nature, concerns itself with one aspect alone: how well or how poorly
am I thinking, choosing and acting? The value of anything and everything else
for me depends entirely on whether I use those conditions to assist me in
living in virtue, and to avoid living in vice.
The
Stoic teaching of indifference tells us that we should never consider any
circumstance of Fortune as itself beneficial or harmful, desirable or
undesirable. Hard experience has long taught me that getting the raise, or
winning the girl, can be just as much of a curse as it can be a blessing. It
has less to do with what I have, than with what I do with what I have. Nor is
absence any worse than presence, because an absence offers just as much of an
opportunity for action.
Once I
have changed the parameters of happiness to what is within my power, to how I
can make good use of any situation for my own character, there is nothing
further I could need, nothing that can hinder me, and nothing beyond my own
wishes. I already have whatever I require, and whatever life can give, or can
take away, is just another chance to live with prudence, fortitude, temperance,
and justice. Do right or wrong to me, and I will be the only one who decides
whether I will do right or wrong in the face of it.
The doctors
and the experts have many fancy names for it, but I have always just called it
the Black Dog. As the years have gone by, the melancholic weight seems only to
get worse, and I have wasted too much of my energy casting blame or cursing
fate. It was only when I began to work with pain, and not against it, that I
could learn to live with more freedom.
It hurt,
but what was I going to do with that hurt? I began to seek out ways, seemingly
insignificant at first, where I could do something good by means of that
experience. It didn’t matter if anyone else knew, because I knew, and my own
estimation is the key to my happiness. The victory only needed to be mine.
Fortune
is itself never really good or bad at all, though what I choose to make of it
can be very good or very bad. Once again, my old musical hero Howard Jones was
probably thinking in Taoist or Buddhist terms, though they could just as well
be Stoic, when he wondered: “Good luck? Bad luck? Who knows?”
36. Does
it suffice?
. . . "What? Does virtue alone
suffice to make you happy?" Why, of course, consummate and god-like virtue
such as this not only suffices, but more than suffices, for when a man is
placed beyond the reach of any desire, what can he possibly lack? If all that
he needs is centered in himself, how can he require anything from without?
He, however, who is only on the road to
virtue, although he may have made great progress along it, nevertheless needs
some favor from fortune while he is still struggling among mere human
interests, while he is untying that knot, and all the bonds which bind him to
mortality.
What, then, is the difference between
them? It is that some are tied more or less tightly by these bonds, and some
have even tied themselves with them as well; whereas he who has made progress
towards the upper regions and raised himself upwards drags a looser chain, and
though not yet free, is yet as good as free.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 16 (tr Stewart)
A good
business sense, the same one that tells us the buyer should beware, reminds us
that if something seems to good to be true, it probably is. Whenever the media
says that the government is going to make things easier for me, or a Nigerian
prince tells me he will share his millions of dollars, I should rightly be
suspicious.
Now why
should I believe these Stoics, who are insisting that happiness is so simple? It
may actually be simple, but it isn’t always easy. It is simple, because all
higher truths admit of simplicity, of being one, and not being divided. It is
also difficult, however, because the weight of my habits and the pull of social
custom tells me it can’t possibly be right. It only seems too good to be true
because we are so out of touch with what is good and true.
In the
world of business, full of liars and crooks, I can never assume that another
person is reliable. In the world of happiness, which depends entirely upon
myself, I am only as reliable as I let myself be. It was when we started being
convinced that happiness was a commodity to buy and sell that it all became a confusing
game. Life sadly ends up being more about the art of playing than the art of
living.
My only
opposition to the simplicity of happiness proceeds from the complexity of
dependence, when I believe I need so many things I don’t really need at all.
Those ties of dependence are easy to bind, but hard to break. I was already
convinced of them as a child, and I still struggle with them as I slouch toward
the end of things. For someone who has made the Stoic Turn, the goal may be
completely clear, but it may also take some effort to get there.
Like
Plato’s philosopher returning into the Cave, or some heretical Rabbi telling us
that we need not worry about what we eat or wear, we will be deemed insane as
soon as we try to strip away the illusions. I know I have begun to free myself
from the ties that bind when I no longer care about being thought insane, and
when I no longer worry about playing the game.
I can’t count
the times I have made a sincere commitment to the fullness of life in the
evening, and I then immediately begin to make excuses for myself the next
morning. That only happens because I haven’t removed all the chains.
Yes,
Nature will suffice. Whatever circumstances may befall me, I need only my own
power of judgment and choice to live with excellence. It may, however, take me
some time to untie the knots, and I will doubt and grumble as I wean myself
from the habits of dependence. One day at a time.
37. Yelping
at philosophy
If, therefore, any one of those dogs
who yelp at philosophy were to say, as they are wont to do, "Why, then, do
you talk so much more bravely than you live? Why do you check your words in the
presence of your superiors, and consider money to be a necessary implement? Why
are you disturbed when you sustain losses, and weep on hearing of the death of
your wife or your friend? Why do you pay regard to common rumor, and feel
annoyed by calumnious gossip?
“Why is your estate more elaborately
kept than its natural use requires? Why do you not dine according to your own
maxims? Why is your furniture smarter than it need be? Why do you drink wine
that is older than yourself? Why are your grounds laid out? Why do you plant trees
that afford nothing except shade? Why does your wife wear in her ears the price
of a rich man's house? Why are your children at school dressed in costly
clothes? Why is it a science to wait upon you at table? Why is your silver
plate not set down anyhow or at random, but skillfully disposed in regular
order, with a superintendent to preside over the carving of the food?"
Add to this, if you like, the questions,
"Why do you own property beyond the seas? Why do you own more than you
know of? It is a shame for you not to know your slaves by sight, for you must
be very neglectful of them if you only own a few, or very extravagant if you
have too many for your memory to retain." . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 17 (tr Stewart)
That a
man will not live up to an ideal does not reflect poorly on the ideal, but upon
the man. As a being of judgment and choice, he can, and he will, fail, and the
reality of such failure makes the dignity of the goal all the more important.
Yet
notice how often we attack the person who points to the true and the good,
instead of considering the value of the true and the good itself. We seem to
like killing the messenger.
This is,
of course, the material fallacy of ad
hominem, of critiquing the arguer, not the argument, and it is so tempting
because it diverts from the question at hand, while also allowing us a perverse
sense of personal superiority. It is a favorite weapon of someone who believes
that an argument is about winning a conflict, not about discovering a truth.
Seneca
has been explaining why our happiness can never be about what happens to us,
but derives from how well we live, and that it is virtue, and not merely
pleasure, that defines the good life. Happiness comes from the inside, not from
the outside. Instead of debating the merits of these claims, the critic wishes
to draw attention to Seneca’s continued concern with external things.
Let us,
for the sake of argument, assume that these claims are true. I believe a good
Stoic, or any good philosopher, must respond with a certain degree of humility
and gratitude. Yes, I don’t always live up to the standards I aspire to, and
thank you, I’m glad you’ve reminded me of all the work I still need to do. Rome
was not built in a day, and a man will only better himself by gradually
rebuilding his habits. A certain sense of good humor can’t hurt, either:
perhaps we can help one another improve together?
I try to
look over these twenty character flaws with as much honesty and humility as I
can muster, and I find myself quite regularly guilty of four of them. Anyone
who knows me will recognize exactly which ones they are. That the remaining
sixteen are largely off of my radar is due less to my credit than the fact that
I have never really been wealthy or influential. That I can recognize my
failings, and know what I must do to correct them, is already progress.
38. Better
than the worst
. . . I will add some reproaches
afterwards, and will bring more accusations against myself than you can think
of.
For the present, I will make you the
following answer: "I am not a wise man, and I will not be one in order to
feed your spite, so do not require me to be on a level with the best of men,
but merely to be better than the worst. I am satisfied, if every day I take
away something from my vices and correct my faults.
“I have not arrived at perfect
soundness of mind, indeed, I never shall arrive at it. I compound palliatives
rather than remedies for my gout, and I am satisfied if it comes at rarer
intervals, and does not shoot so painfully.
“Compared with your feet, which are
lame, I am a racer."
I make this speech, not on my own
behalf, for I am steeped in vices of every kind, but on behalf of one who has
made some progress in virtue.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 17 (tr Stewart)
A common
characteristic of an arrogant man is his belief that he can really do no wrong.
You may find him telling you that he might have been in error, but listen to
his words closely. His flaw is hardly ever a flaw, because he says he acted
with too much honesty, or kindness, or understanding, and in criticizing
himself, he is actually praising himself for just being too good. Since he
doesn’t really make mistakes, he then assumes other people must think in
exactly the same way.
Seneca
isn’t claiming to be without weaknesses, because he knows that every man is
subject to failure. A good life is hardly a perfect state, but a constant
process of learning, of growth, of improvement. It is never about being the
best, but always about striving to be better. Each of us, as they say, will
inevitably fall down, but the success is in getting up, dusting ourselves off,
and trying again. The doing and the living is itself the goal.
We never
really cure ourselves of making mistakes, because that would mean no longer
being creatures moved by our own thinking and choices, though with effort we
become better at managing our weaknesses. Sometimes the progress seems so slow,
and sometimes we seem to slide backwards, but even the slightest effort, and the
smallest improvement, is an essential part of the practice of living well.
A worse
man is content to think he is already good, while a better man always struggles
to raise himself higher. Remember that Socrates learned that he was wise
because he could admit he was ignorant, just as any man who aspires to virtue recognizes
all of his vices.
I
sometimes feel that I carry with me the burden of far too many terrible choices,
many that make me squirm in shame, some that seem downright irredeemable. There
are weak times when I wish I could erase them, though a dose of Stoic common
sense can usually sets me straight.
It is
not only that they did happen, but also that every one of them played a
necessary part in becoming who I now am, and in what good I have within me.
Each was an opportunity to become better. That does not justify an error, but
it allows me to transform an error into something good. While I cannot go back
and remove a mistake, I can always continue making right out of something
wrong.
39. Living
without spite.
"You talk one way," objects
our adversary, "and live another."
You most spiteful of creatures, you who
always show the bitterest hatred to the best of men, this reproach was flung at
Plato, at Epicurus, at Zeno.
For all these declared how they ought
to live, not how they did live. I speak of virtue, not of myself, and when I
blame vices, I blame my own first of all. When I have the power, I shall live
as I ought to do.
Spite, however deeply steeped in venom,
shall not keep me back from what is best. That poison itself with which you
bespatter others, with which you choke yourselves, shall not hinder me from
continuing to praise that life which I do not, indeed, lead, but which I know I
ought to lead, from loving virtue and from following after her, albeit a long
way behind her and with halting gait. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 18 (tr Stewart)
The sort
of critic who looks first to your weakness will also be quite ready to consider
you a hypocrite. While a man who struggles and fails is at least sincere in his
goals, the hypocrite knows full well that he is a fraud, but sees nothing wrong
with this. The show of noble appearance is simply another means for him to get the
base things that he wants. I do wonder how often we quickly assume hypocrisy in
others because we are so familiar with it from ourselves.
I must
always remember that the malice in people’s hearts appears to them, in however
twisted a way, to be a good. The adversaries that Seneca faces are not so
different from the adversaries we all face every day, because what they all
share in common is the belief that the only way they can make themselves better
is to make less of others. It proceeds from the ignorance that for one person
to win, another must lose. I once foolishly thought I just had the bad luck of
only running into such people in my neck of the woods, but I learned that such
an error could be found anywhere and everywhere.
It is
easy to meet hatred from others with hatred from myself, but the bitter irony
is that while another may have called me inferior, I will only make myself
inferior by responding in kind, and I will really become that hypocrite if I
preach virtue but pursue vice. Like any passion divorced from sound judgment,
spite becomes infectious. Just as he is called to find the good in any
circumstance, the Stoic must transform evil done to him into good done by
him.
Other
people may try to keep me from improvement, but that is on them. I will be the
only one who decides if I will spit poison. When I am reminded that I am not
good enough, and another takes pleasure in having targeted a weakness, I can
tell myself that what I know I must seek never needs to be hindered by what
others might think or say. The progress of a good life will continue only as
long as I don’t let myself be distracted by spite.
40. Virtue,
not poverty
. . . Am I to expect that evil speaking
will respect anything, seeing that it respected neither Rutilius nor Cato?
Will anyone care about being thought
too rich by men for whom Diogenes the Cynic was not poor enough? That most
energetic philosopher fought against all the desires of the body, and was
poorer even than the other Cynics, in that besides having given up possessing
anything he had also given up asking for anything.
Yet they reproached him for not being
sufficiently in want, as though it were poverty, not virtue, of which he
professed knowledge.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 18 (tr Stewart)
Rome had
many base men, but it also had many great men. Rutilius Rufus found himself
exiled for defending the citizens against the corruption of tax collectors, and
Cato the Younger felt it better to die than to live in a state dominated by the
arrogance of Julius Caesar. Like so many who stood for what they thought was
right over what was convenient, they were vilified and condemned.
Diogenes
of Sinope was well known for his extreme criticism of a society that he thought
was dominated by a lust for wealth, power, and privilege. While many found his
behavior shocking and scandalous, this apparently didn’t stop people from also insisting
that he was never quite poor enough to live up to his own standards. One
wonders how a man who lived in a barrel, and who discarded his only bowl after
seeing another man drink from his hands, could possibly have given up anything
more.
I recall
reading two articles at roughly the same time, one of which argued that Teresa
of Calcutta had failed to do enough for the dying, while the other claimed that
she had done far too much to keep them from dying. I have heard my different
leaders tell me that the problem with the poor in America is that they have too
little to survive on, and also that they have far too much. An important person
once told me that teachers were the most valuable assets to any society, but he
also insisted that they were grossly overpaid.
The
problem, I think, is that we are quick to criticize without any sound moral
measure, without a sense of right and wrong to guide our judgments. Diogenes
wasn’t trying to teach people how to be impoverished, but he was rather trying
to teach them how to be virtuous; being poor was hardly itself the point, but
being good was.
Mother
Teresa would have been baffled by the criticisms of the social planners,
because she thought that the dignity of every individual human being could
hardly be judged by graphs and statistics. I myself am deeply confused when we
demand that people make something of themselves, but then never give them the
opportunities to do so; a man cannot pull himself up by his bootstraps if he
has no chance to buy himself any boots. A teacher, or a student, or any person
at all, should never be thought of as a commodity subject to the greed of the
market, to be used only as far as they make us a profit.
Like an
armchair quarterback, the critic will find something flawed about you, whatever
you might do, because he simply likes to point out what is wrong. He has no
room for what is right, because that would require that he be constructive, not
destructive. It is always easier to dismiss a perceived evil than to embrace a
true good.
The
Stoic, like any decent man, begins and ends his estimation of anything by
asking how it can encourage us in being virtuous, and how it can discourage us
from being vicious.
His moral
compass always points to the pole of virtue. It is never about being rich or
poor, or being of one or another social, racial, or political persuasion, but
about aiming at that excellence that fulfills our shared human condition. A man
is not good because of what he does or doesn’t have, but by what he does with
what he does or doesn’t have.
41. Departing
from life
They say that Diodorus, the Epicurean
philosopher, who within these last few days put an end to his life with his own
hand, did not act according to the precepts of Epicurus, in cutting his throat.
Some choose to regard this act as the
result of madness, others of recklessness. He, meanwhile, happy and filled with
the consciousness of his own goodness, has borne testimony to himself by his
manner of departing from life, has commended the repose of a life spent at
anchor in a safe harbor, and has said what you do not like to hear, because you
too ought to do it.
"I've lived, I've run the race
which Fortune set me.". . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 19 (tr Stewart)
The issue
of suicide was clearly as important and divisive for the Ancients as it is for
us Moderns. Seneca himself ended up taking his own life, having been ordered to
do so by Emperor Nero, who believed that Seneca had been involved in an
assassination plot. Socrates, of course, at the order of the Athenians, drank
the hemlock.
The
question is not whether we will die, because it is in our nature to be mortal,
or even when we will die, because how well we live surely takes precedence over
how long we live. I suggest that what matters more is how and why we die, or
when it might be right to sacrifice our lives, or allow our lives to end, or
even to hasten that end.
The most
helpful Stoic guidance for me comes from Musonius Rufus, when he offers this
measure:
One
who by living is of use to many has not the right to choose to die, unless
by dying he may be of use to more. (Fragment 29)
I learned long ago never to be
dismissive of those who consider taking their own lives, or conversely never to
romanticize such an act. I have known a good number of people who have
attempted it, and some who have succeeded, and there were a number of times
many years ago when, tormented by the pain of the Black Dog, I stood there
right at the edge myself.
I know that every life is worth
living, and I understand that my own good is in the merit of my actions, not in
some balance sheet of pleasure and pain. At the same time, I can consider how
someone is feeling and thinking when he is faced with the prospect of jumping
from a burning building.
I remind myself that I should never
want to die, to cease to exist simply for its own sake, but that I should be
gladly willing to suffer death if I must do so to have lived with virtue. It is
my judgment and intention about my circumstances that will make all the
difference between courage and cowardice.
I know
nothing about the specific case of Diodorus, and so I can hardly judge it, but
whether what he did was right or wrong, I think I see what Seneca admires in
him. He knew above all else that he had done what life had asked him to do, and
he was willing to embrace his own end in good conscience and on his own terms.
I am
hardly an old man, but I learned recently that I was suffering from heart
failure. I decided I would refuse certain treatments where I judged the burden or
harm to be completely out of proportion to any benefits, and I asked that I not
be resuscitated if and when my heart stopped beating. Some people I knew were
horrified by this, and assumed I was giving up. Others nodded quietly in
comprehension.
I will not
choose to hasten my end, but I will not vainly resist it either. Such an
attitude is only possible for me because I remain convinced that I should always
choose quality over quantity.
42. Crosses
and lusts
. . .You argue about the life and death
of another, and yelp at the name of men whom some peculiarly noble quality has
rendered great, just as tiny curs do at the approach of strangers.
For it is to your interest that no one
should appear to be good, as if virtue in another were a reproach to all your
crimes. You enviously compare the glories of others with your own dirty
actions, and do not understand how greatly to your disadvantage it is to
venture to do so. For if they who follow after virtue are greedy, lustful, and
fond of power, what must you be, who hate the very name of virtue?
You say that no one acts up to his
professions, or lives according to the standard that he sets up in his
discourses. What wonder, seeing that the words they speak are brave, gigantic,
and able to weather all the storms that wreck mankind, whereas they themselves
are struggling to tear themselves away from crosses into which each one of you
is driving his own nail.
Yet men who are crucified hang from one
single pole, but these who punish themselves are divided between as many
crosses as they have lusts, but yet are given to evil speaking, and are so
magnificent in their contempt of the vices of others that I should suppose that
they had none of their own, were it not that some criminals when on the gibbet
spit upon the spectators.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 19 (tr Stewart)
There
was a time when I would hardly think about the relationship between what was
done to me and what I did. I would always complain bitterly, of course, when I
felt that others were hurting me, but I would still seek satisfaction when I
was hurting them. My selfishness and ignorance went hand in hand, because I
refused to see that I was demanding I be exempt from the very same expectations
I had for others, and I resented it deeply if someone else was actually better
than me.
It took
hitting bottom, something I complained about then but consider a blessing now,
to even begin to change my ways. It is still very much a work in progress, but
it begins with the connected insights that I do not become better when I think
worse of others, but actually only make myself worse when I wish to drag them
down. I have always been my own worst enemy.
I do
indeed make it harder for others when I put obstacles in their way to a good
life, and I would have seen that fairly easily if I had just switched places
with them from my own perspective. Yet while they can still choose to struggle,
to improve, to make themselves better in the face of my pettiness, I have
already defeated myself. I have disparaged their virtue, but I have abandoned
my own virtue by being exactly what I claim to hate.
The Roman
practice of crucifixion was truly barbaric, because it was not just a
punishment, or a means of execution, but a way of deliberately inflicting
horrible suffering and humiliation on the victims. I am hardly any different
when I inflict pain on others for my own satisfaction. Though I may string another
man up, or nail him to a post, I bind myself to a new cross of self-torture over
and over, every time I choose to act with malice and vice.
43. To
climb a steep path
“Philosophers do not carry into effect
all that they teach."
No, but they effect much good by their
teaching, by the noble thoughts which they conceive in their minds; would,
indeed, that they could act up to their talk. What could be happier than they
would be?
But in the meanwhile, you have no right
to despise good sayings and hearts full of good thoughts. Men deserve praise
for engaging in profitable studies, even though they stop short of producing
any results. Why need we wonder if those who begin to climb a steep path do not
succeed in ascending it very high?
Yet, if you are a man, look with
respect on those who attempt great things, even though they fall. It is the act
of a generous spirit to proportion its efforts not to its own strength, but to
that of human nature, to entertain lofty aims, and to conceive plans which are
too vast to be carried into execution even by those who are endowed with
gigantic intellects, who appoint for themselves the following rules:
"I will look upon death or upon a
comedy with the same expression of countenance.
“I will submit to labors, however great
they may be, supporting the strength of my body by that of my mind.
“I will despise riches when I have them
as much as when I have them not; if they are elsewhere I will not be more
gloomy, if they sparkle around me I will not be more lively than I should
otherwise be.
“Whether Fortune comes or goes I will take
no notice of her. I will view all lands as though they belong to me, and my own
as though they belonged to all mankind. . . .”
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 20 (tr Stewart)
Wisdom
will set the goal of the good life for us, and philosophy will be the companion
to help us work toward the goal. Action will proceed from understanding, though
it will do so by degrees, and it will sometimes fall short. No matter. The
success is in the effort itself, and the steep path to the summit makes the
climb all the more worthy and noble.
My mind
will often race far ahead of my deeds, though this should hardly be a
discouragement. I must set my sights high, but also be fully understanding of where
I stand now and what I have the strength to do.
I find
great comfort in Seneca’s rules, not only at those times I may succeed, but
especially at those times when I fail.
I should
have no fear of death, and I should even laugh at death, because it is hardly a
dreadful thing. It should only serve to remind me of what is good, because to
know that I can die at any moment is also to know that I must pursue the joy of
virtue in every moment.
I should
remember that the value of any of my efforts will be essentially defined by how
I think about them. Where my estimation finds something good, there will be
benefit, and where my estimation sees only bad, there will be harm. Nothing in
this life is interesting or boring, valuable or useless, helpful or a
hindrance, except in the way the mind chooses to understand it or not to
understand it.
I should
always define myself by what is within me, and not by what is outside of me. I
should never wish to be rich, and I should never wish to be poor, because the
presence or absence of possessions is not the fulfillment of my nature, or the
measure of my happiness.
I should
never look to Fortune as my guide, since what she gives and what she takes away
are beyond my power. I should even cease to think of the difference between
what belongs to me and what belongs to another. The true goods that Nature
provides are to be shared by all, not gifted only to some.
44. Born
for others
“. . . I will so live as to remember that
I was born for others, and I will thank Nature on this account: for in what
fashion could she have done better for me? She has given me alone to all, and
all to me alone.
“Whatever I may possess, I will neither
hoard it greedily nor squander it recklessly. I will think that I have no
possessions so real as those that I have given away to deserving people. I will
not reckon benefits by their magnitude or number, or by anything except the
value set upon them by the receiver. I never will consider a gift to be a large
one if it is bestowed upon a worthy object.
“I will do nothing because of public
opinion, but everything because of conscience. Whenever I do anything alone by
myself I will believe that the eyes of the Roman people are upon me while I do
it.
“In eating and drinking my object shall
be to quench the desires of Nature, not to fill and empty my belly. . . .”
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 20 (tr Stewart)
The
principles of ethics are much richer and deeper than any politics or economics,
because they are concerned not merely with the circumstances of power and
wealth, but with the very purpose of our human nature.
So much
of what we see around us tries to insist that man is made to acquire, to
possess, to consume. The Stoic, however, stands by the basic truth that man is
defined not by what comes to him, but by what he does. He is made, therefore,
not to receive for himself, but to give of himself.
This
flies in the face of accepted custom, and one cannot take a money seeker, a
power broker, or a fame follower and merely dress him up like a Stoic. These
views are incompatible, because they consider man as ordered toward opposing
ends. I have slowly discovered that I only really began to appreciate life once
I started to think of myself as a creature made not to dominate, but to love.
The
value of anything is to be measured not by its financial worth, or by the profit
of wealth or influence it can give to me, but by its moral worth, how it can be
used to improve the character of both others and myself. Consider a man to be a
good investor if he assists others in their happiness, and consider him rich if
he owns his own deeds.
Once I
begin to measure my actions through the approval or disapproval of others, I
have already strayed from the path. I am here to care for others, and to live
with them openly, but I am not ruled by their esteem. I only need to follow my
awareness of right and wrong, as informed by Nature, to live the good life.
Though people
all around me may want to devour more and more, Nature is always asking me to
take and enjoy what I need, but never to want any more than I may need. I can
only begin to see temperance and self-control as a great benefit when I no
longer see myself as a consumer of good, but as an agent of good.
45. Being
agreeable
“. . . I will be agreeable with my
friends, gentle and mild to my foes. I will grant pardon before I am asked for
it, and will meet the wishes of honorable men half way.
“I will bear in mind that the world is
my native city, that its governors are the gods, and that they stand above and
around me, criticizing whatever I do or say.
“Whenever either Nature demands my
breath again, or reason bids me to dismiss it, I will quit this life, calling
all to witness that I have loved a good conscience, and good pursuits, and that
no one's freedom, my own least of all, has been impaired through me.”
He who sets up these as the rules of
his life will soar aloft and strive to make his way to the gods: in truth, even
if he fails, he fails in a high endeavor. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 20 (tr Stewart)
Think of
how many times we have all heard that phrase, or used it ourselves: “Well, I’m
a good person. Or at least I try to be.” In and of itself, it seems a perfectly
decent thing to say. I have often wondered, however, what we all really mean
when we say it.
For as
long as I can remember, others have told me that I must be kind, caring, nice,
respectful, or agreeable. As the admittedly sort of annoying fellow who has
always asked “why?” as long as he could speak, I was regularly told that this
was simply the proper and acceptable thing to do. “Be nice” becomes something
we say quite often, but we don’t always reflect upon it. It also saddens me to
see that we don’t even do it nearly as often as we might think.
I always
feel like a terrible curmudgeon when I ask that “why?” question, though I do it
not because I want people to be horrible to one another, but because I am
looking for something to give us a good reason to love one another, something
that will help us stay the course whenever difficulty may arise. For myself, I
know I have struggled between being seen as good in order to get what I want
from others, and being good to others regardless of how it is seen.
I often
distinguish between two different senses of being “agreeable”, and it boils
down to a very real difference between abuse and respect. I intend no
exaggeration, but I do believe that if I act toward others with the profit of
my own circumstances in mind, treating them as a means to my end, then I am a
player, a manipulator, and yes, even an abuser. If I act toward others with
their own good in mind, treating them as ends in themselves, then I may
actually be practicing genuine respect.
Though I
am, of course, only playing within the context of the English word, there is a
contrast between being agreeable so that others will agree with me, and being
agreeable because I am agreeing with Nature.
To be a
good person, I must understand that my fellows are made just like me, sharing the
same purpose, and worthy of the same dignity. I won’t always come across as
likeable when I seek their happiness, but I should always desire what is good
for them, however that may change my own selfish utility.
Accordingly,
there is no “us” versus “them” in the order of Nature. There is only “all of us”.
Whether we choose to accept it or not, we are all here in the service of
Nature, and of the Divine that orders Nature.
To
remember my mortality, memento mori, is
a wonderful aid in this endeavor, because it isn’t all about me, but about how
I, as one part, can help to serve the whole, the fulfillment of all the parts.
I will end when Nature calls me back, or when my conscience tells me it is
right to give myself for another. I have begun to expect no other reward beyond
having run the race as best I can.
46. Sickly
eyes
. . . But you, who hate both virtue and
those who practice it, do nothing at which we need be surprised, for sickly eyes
cannot bear the sun, nocturnal creatures avoid the brightness of day, and at
its first dawning become bewildered and all betake themselves to their dens
together.
Creatures that fear the light hide
themselves in crevices. So croak away, and exercise your miserable tongues in
reproaching good men.
Open wide your jaws, bite hard. You
will break many teeth before you make any impression.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 20 (tr Stewart)
Great sages,
poets, and artists have long used the image of light as a symbol for the truth,
and the image of the eye as a symbol for the mind. Just as light makes objects visible
to the eye, so truth makes reality intelligible to the mind, and as the sun is
the source of all light, the Divine is the source of all truth. Separated from
light the eye is blind, and separated from truth the mind is ignorant.
Though
the eye is made to see, and the mind is made to understand, there are many ways
that either can be hindered. If another object is blocking my sight, I must
move around it or away from it. If the eye is diseased, I must seek a cure. If
my vision has become so accustomed to darkness, I must slowly adjust to the
light.
When I
was younger, my father would wryly remind me that I should be a child of light,
not of darkness. I assumed he was referring to my staying out all hours of the
night getting up to no good with the wrong sorts of people, and he was most
certainly speaking of that. Yet I am also sure he meant it not just literally,
but also figuratively. My being nocturnal was not just about the time of day,
but also about my whole attitude.
Disappointment,
pain, or fear have sometimes made me decide to close my eyes to what is true
and good. It is a form of denial, perhaps, or of running away, but at such
times I have also become bitter and negative. Everything may appear dark and
grey, and so, as Seneca says, I croak, I exercise my miserable tongue, and I
break my own teeth biting down.
The
longer I cut myself off from what is true and good, from what Nature asks and
provides, the more I wallow in darkness and ignorance, and the harder it
becomes to return to the light. There were times when I had become so used to
ignorance and resentment that wisdom and charity seemed to burn.
Being a
pale Irish fellow, I figured out long ago that when the warm weather comes
along, I just need to spend a day out in the sun. My skin will turn bright red,
and I will feel uncomfortable for a time, but that toughens me up for the rest
of the summer. I’ve had to do the same with my heart and mind a few times, to
get them back to state where they can appreciate what is right and decent.
I have
sadly seen too many people I love crawl into the dark over the years, and light
now seems toxic to them. I often feel like I would want nothing more than to rouse
them from the crevices, and help them to walk their way in the daytime, until
their eyes can once again grow accustomed to brightness.
47. Despising
fortune
"But how is it that this man
studies philosophy and nevertheless lives the life of a rich man? Why does he
say that wealth ought to be despised and yet possess it?
“That life should be despised, and yet
live?
“That health should be despised, and
yet guard it with the utmost care, and wish it to be as good as possible?
“Does he consider banishment to be an
empty name, and say, ‘What evil is there in changing one country for another?’
and yet, if permitted, does he not grow old in his native land?
“Does he declare that there is no
difference between a longer and a shorter time, and yet, if he is not
prevented, lengthen out his life and flourish in a green old age?"
His answer is, that these things ought
to be despised, not that he should not possess them, but that he should not
possess them with fear and trembling. He does not drive them away from him, but
when they leave him he says farewell to them without concern.
Where, indeed, can Fortune invest
riches more securely than in a place from where they can always be recovered
without any squabble with their trustee?
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 21 (tr Stewart)
I
believe that one of the great misunderstandings about Stoicism, and about any
philosophy that treats virtue as the measure of man, concerns what it means to
“despise” money, or any of the gifts of Fortune.
When I
love something, I recognize that it is good, and I desire it. Now I might
assume that the only contrary to love can be hate, in which case I recognize
that something is bad, and I avoid it. There is a third option, in that I
recognize that something is in itself neither good not bad, and I should
therefore neither desire it nor avoid it. This third view is the Stoic concept
of indifference, and it is what Stoic texts mean when they speak of despising
Fortune.
The
question is not whether we will, or should, possess wealth, but whether we will
care or worry about it for its own sake. This holds true for health, for the
comforts of home, for a long life, and for anything else in our circumstances. These
things may be given, or they may be taken away, but we are called throughout to
think only of the ways we can use both their presence and absence to the
improvement of moral character.
Some
people might assume that if I am not deliberately seeking wealth, then I must
be trying to avoid it. Other people might assume that if I happen to be
wealthy, that must be something I am dedicated to. Neither needs to be the
case. I often say that I have known rich men who are good men, but I have never
known a man to be good because he is rich.
Now we
all know that most people will appear more than happy to take advantage of an
upturn in their fortunes. Give a man more money, and he will most likely start
thinking about what to spend it on, where to invest, how to build his security
and his comfort. But take the money away, and he will most likely worry and
fret about losing everything. Both reactions are misguided, because both assume
that value is in the possession, and both reactions offers no benefit, because both
define happiness through the presence of something external.
The
result is that all fortune, both from things we receive or lose, will not help
a vicious man be happy, since he will use fortune poorly. Conversely, all
fortune, both from things we receive or lose, will help a virtuous man be
happy, since he will order fortune wisely.
It is
also fitting that only someone virtuous will actually make a good steward or
caretaker of wealth. He will understand that any benefits to be derived from
Fortune are directed to the improvement of the soul, and not about lining his
wallet. He will not be troubled about returning
what he had been given.
48. Preference,
not love
. . . Marcus Cato, when he was praising
Curius and Coruncanius and that century in which the possession of a few small
silver coins was an offence which was punished by the Censor, himself owned
four million sesterces; a less fortune, no doubt, than that of Crassus, but
larger than of Cato the Censor.
If the amounts be compared, he had
outstripped his great-grandfather further than he himself was outdone by
Crassus, and if still greater riches had fallen to his lot, he would not have
spurned them, for the wise man does not think himself unworthy of any chance
presents.
He does not love riches, but he prefers
to have them. He does not receive them into his spirit, but only into his
house, nor does he cast away from him what he already possesses, but keeps
them, and is willing that his virtue should receive a larger subject matter for
its exercise.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 21 (tr Stewart)
I can
hardly make any profound judgments about Roman politics, and I am ignorant of
all the subtleties of Seneca’s own political thinking. These references,
however, are surely intended to ask the reader to consider the difference
between good men who happen to be rich, and bad men who love being rich.
Cato the
Younger, and his great-grandfather Cato the Elder, were both very wealthy men,
but Seneca admired both of them greatly for their character. It is interesting
that Cato the Younger praised Manius Curius Dentatus, a consul of the third
century BC who was known for his great frugality, and who, legend tells us,
once said he preferred eating his turnips to receiving political bribes,
because he thought it better to rule rich men than to be one himself.
There seems
quite a difference between the prosperous Cato and the thrifty Curius, but I
suggest that we are meant to see that this hardly matters. Curius wasn’t good
because he was poor, and Cato wasn’t bad because he was rich. They were both
good men because they pursued virtue, regardless of how much they possessed.
No, the
real contrast is between Cato and his contemporary, Crassus. While both men
were rich, though Crassus was apparently richer, the similarity ends there.
Cato, a follower of Stoicism, stood for the values of the Roman Republic
against the First Triumvirate of Caesar, Pompey, and Crassus. Seneca viewed
Cato as a man of moral principle, but Crassus was the Roman equivalent of a modern
real estate mogul, who mixed his desire for personal profit with political
power plays.
Cato and
Crassus were similar in their circumstances, but radically different in their
priorities. We have all seen the difference between those who use their wealth
to serve others, and those who use others to serve their wealth.
A wise
man does not love money, and he does not seek it for its own sake, though he
may well choose to prefer it. This may well seem like a petty distinction of
semantics, and we can use whatever terminology we like, but there is a real and
critical difference between want and preference. The Stoic should want only
virtue, and avoid only vice. He should be indifferent to all other things, and
make use of them insofar as they help him to be virtuous and not vicious.
Accordingly, I should only want to be a good man, not a rich man, or a powerful
man, or a popular man.
But let
us say all things are equal, and I could be a good man whether I was rich or
poor. I will take either circumstance, but I would most likely prefer the
option of wealth over poverty, health over sickness, a long life over a short
life, many friends over no friends. These are all certainly more pleasant, and
they might appear to offer me greater opportunities. Where a condition does not
conflict with virtue, I will rightly have the free choice of a preference, but
any preference must always be relative to and defer to virtue.
My own
silly way of remembering this is that I can take it or leave it, but if I don’t
have to leave it, I’ll gladly take it.
I
propose that Curius was a virtuous man who preferred
poverty, and Cato was a virtuous man who preferred
wealth, while Cassius was a vicious man who wanted
wealth. It all reduces to whether I love something external for itself, or if I
love virtue and also welcome something external.
My own
experience is that the absence of fortune may actually be preferable to the
presence of fortune far more often than we think, and in this regard I am drawn
more to Curius. I find I usually prefer turnips to the burden of wealth. But
that is a reflection for another time.
49. Wisdom
and wealth
Who can doubt, however, that the wise
man, if he is rich, has a wider field for the development of his powers than if
he is poor, seeing that in the latter case the only virtue which he can display
is that of neither being perverted nor crushed by his poverty, whereas if he
has riches, he will have a wide field for the exhibition of temperance,
generosity, laboriousness, methodical arrangement, and grandeur.
The wise man will not despise himself,
however short of stature he may be, but nevertheless he will wish to be tall. Even
though he be feeble and one-eyed he may be in good health, yet he would prefer
to have bodily strength, and that too, while he knows all the while that he has
something which is even more powerful: he will endure illness, and will hope
for good health.
For some things, though they may be
trifles compared with the sum total, and though they may be taken away without
destroying the chief good, yet they add somewhat to that constant cheerfulness
which arises from virtue. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 22 (tr Stewart)
This is
the sort of Stoic passage that, quite honestly, makes me a bit nervous at
first. This concern ends up hardly being about Seneca’s argument at all, and is
really about my own weakness.
For the
wise man, wealth can become a means for greater good, and an opportunity to
practice greater virtue. By having more at his disposal, he can do more for
others, and he can exercise a greatness of character that would be impossible
if he was poor. In poverty he may learn to order himself, but in plenty he can
also give order to what is around him.
Things
like wealth, health, or strength, though they are not in themselves the highest
good, can certainly be preferred as a way of aiding us in practicing the
highest good. The Stoic will embrace the chance to employ them, though because
his goal is far greater, he will also gladly accept their loss.
I
immediately see the soundness in the argument, but I question the soundness in
myself. Everything here hinges upon the premise that a man of wealth and means
must first be wise, he must seek to do good above all else, and he must
recognize that his position is about service, not about being served. It
requires something that seems quite difficult: possessing great fortune, but
not loving great fortune.
How many
such people can there truly be? I know I am not one of them. I know that even
King Solomon, for all of his wisdom, succumbed to the temptations of wealth,
idolatry, and lust.
The
question is really much like the challenge of Plato’s Philosopher King. Because
bad people are attracted to wealth and power, how can we assure that good
people are inspired to give right purpose to wealth and power? How can we be
certain they will not in turn be drawn into greed and lust themselves?
Some see
political corruption, so they advocate the abolition of government. Others see
the abuse of money, so they advocate the abolition of wealth. Yet instead of
assuming the worst of men, can we not work to make the best of men? It isn’t
wealth or power that is the problem, but the fact that we are greedy and
selfish with our wealth and power. That is precisely why the Stoic argues that
we must build character above all else, so that all other things in life can be
used for benefit.
That I
am skeptical about rich men being good means only that I know I am not good
enough to be rich. I should see this is a call to become better, not to merely
accept what is worse. I should never say that something cannot be found if I’ve
always been looking for it in the wrong place. The solutions to the struggles
of this life are not just economic, legal, or political, but are rather
essentially moral. Inspire virtue in men first in order, and the rest will take
care of itself.
50. Placing
riches
. . . Riches encourage and brighten up
such a man just as a sailor is delighted at a favorable wind that bears him on
his way, or as people feel pleasure at a fine day or at a sunny spot in the
cold weather.
What wise man, I mean of our school,
whose only good is virtue, can deny that even these matters which we call
neither good nor bad have in themselves a certain value, and that some of them
are preferable to others? To some of them we show a certain amount of respect,
and to some a great deal. Do not, then, make any mistake: riches belong to the
class of desirable things.
"Why then," you say, "do
you laugh at me, since you place them in the same position that I do?"
Do you wish to know how different the position
is in which we place them? If my riches leave me, they will carry away with
them nothing except themselves. You will be bewildered and will seem to be left
without yourself if they should pass away from you.
With me riches occupy a certain place,
but with you they occupy the highest place of all. In the end, my riches belong
to me, but you belong to your riches.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 22 (tr Stewart)
We will
indeed find good people who also happen to be wealthy, though we may not
immediately recognize them. We are so used to being impressed with the
appearance of prosperity that we often fail to look to the character beneath. The
money itself isn’t really praiseworthy at all, but what someone may do with it
certainly can be.
I had
the honor of knowing a fellow who had made a massive fortune in business, and
who once offered to write a blank check to a small college that was trying to
recover from years of mismanagement.
There
were certain conditions, however, and they were not negotiable. No, he wasn’t
asking that a building be named after him, or for an honorary degree, or any
tax perks. Instead, he asked that the gift, which could easily have ended up
being in the tens of millions, be completely anonymous, that the top-heavy
administration be cleaned up, that tuition remain low enough for working
families to afford, that faculty and staff receive a fair wage, and that the
school stick to its mission of helping young people learn to think, not just
getting them entry-level jobs.
Each and
every one of those requirements revealed character, because they came from a
commitment to the true purpose of liberal arts learning and a respect for human
dignity. It wasn’t just about giving money, but about using it to encourage
human excellence.
The
college administration refused his offer, and it was easy to see why. They
surely felt that it threatened their own power, and they probably assumed the donor
was interested in the same sort of empire building that they were. What they
failed to see was that not everyone placed wealth in the same position that
they did.
You will
recognize in what sort of esteem a man holds money by looking beyond the possessions
themselves. Remove all the trappings and look at the soul within him. What does
he value, and what is his purpose? Does he rule over his property with wisdom
and fairness, or does his property rule him through vanity and greed? If you
took away all the prosperity, would you find just an empty shell of man, now
completely lost without all his fine playthings, or would you find a commitment
to character that doesn’t ebb and flow with the fickle circumstances of the
world?
I have
known both sorts of people, and I have gradually learned that our own dignity
will rise or fall by whether we give priority to virtue or to possessions.
Wealth that is not in the service of justice will only enslave us.
51. Honorably
come by, and honorably spent
Cease, then, forbidding philosophers to
possess money; no one has condemned wisdom to poverty.
The philosopher may own ample wealth,
but will not own wealth that which has been torn from another, or which is
stained with another's blood. His must be obtained without wronging any man,
and without its being won by base means; it must be alike honorably come by and
honorably spent, and must be such as spite alone could shake its head at.
Raise it to whatever figure you please,
it will still be an honorable possession, if, while it includes much which
every man would like to call his own, there be nothing which any one can say is
his own.
Such a man will not forfeit his right
to the favor of Fortune, and will neither boast of his inheritance nor blush
for it if it was honorably acquired. Yet he will have something to boast of, if
he throw his house open, let all his countrymen come among his property, and
say, "If any one recognizes here anything belonging to him, let him take
it."
What a great man, how excellently rich
will he be, if after this speech he possesses as much as he had before! I say,
then, that if he can safely and confidently submit his accounts to the scrutiny
of the people, and no one can find in them any item upon which he can lay hands,
such a man may boldly and unconcealedly enjoy his riches. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 23 (tr Stewart)
Never
blame wealth for the abuses of bad men. Blame bad men for the abuses of wealth.
Fortune
may offer us all sorts of benefits, but what will make all the difference is
how we came to acquire them, and how we proceed to use them. Just as you will be
able to discern a man’s character when he is in a state of loss, you will also
be able to discern his character when he is in a state of plenty.
I
suspect that some of us resent wealth because we do not have it, but the
solution to this is recognizing that it isn’t the wealth that will ever make us
happy. Others of us are disgusted by wealth because we see the vices of so many
people who are given much, but the solution to this is recognizing that we
should rather be disgusted by the vices.
Have we
won fortune with justice, and are we spending it with justice? This means more
than simply having worked hard, or worked cleverly, for a reward, and it means
more than just having the appearance of respectability. Justice always demands
that we never take more than we deserve, and we never give less than another
deserves. Justice may even be tempered with mercy and charity, and we can then take
less than we deserve, and give more than another deserves.
Too many
of us take for granted what we inherit, we confuse earning with stealing, and
we are wasteful with what we possess. We are outraged when someone takes what
we think is ours, but we call it good business when we take what belongs to
others. Now getting angry about this will change nothing, but starting to show
love to my neighbor is the beginning of a cure.
I adore
Seneca’s challenge to throw open our coffers to any rightful claimants, though
I wonder who would do so with integrity. We fear our rivals and competitors
because we know full well that we have wronged them. Though our gains are often
ill-gotten, nothing need stop us from giving back what we have taken. It starts
with changing our own thinking about what is true and good, and proceeds
through action inspired by giving and receiving honorably.
52. Giving
to good men
. . . The wise man will not allow a
single ill-won penny to cross his threshold, yet he will not refuse or close his
door against great riches, if they are the gift of fortune and the product of
virtue.
What reason has he for grudging them
good quarters? Let them come and be his guests. He will neither brag of them
nor hide them away: the one is the part of a silly, the other of a cowardly and
paltry spirit, which, as it were, muffles up a good thing in its lap.
Neither will he, as I said before, turn
them out of his house, for what will he say? Will he say, "You are useless,"
or "I do not know how to use riches?" As he is capable of performing
a journey upon his own feet, but yet would prefer to mount a carriage, just so
he will be capable of being poor, yet will wish to be rich; he will own wealth,
but will view it as an uncertain possession which will someday fly away from
him. He will not allow it to be a burden either to himself or to any one else.
He will give it—why do you prick up
your ears? Why do you open your pockets?—he will give it either to good men or
to those whom it may make into good men.
He will give it after having taken the
utmost pains to choose those who are fittest to receive it, as becomes one who
bears in mind that he ought to give an account of what he spends as well as of
what he receives.
He will give for good and commendable
reasons, for a gift ill bestowed counts as a shameful loss. He will have an
easily opened pocket, but not one with a hole in it, so that much may be taken
out of it, yet nothing may fall out of it.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 23 (tr Stewart)
I
imagine the Rome of Seneca’s time was quite similar to our own day and age,
with people rushing about trying to gain as much money, status, and influence
for themselves as they possibly could. Friends readily became nothing but tools
for advancement, and profit held sway over justice. It would be easy to assume at
first that Seneca is condoning such a life, simply because he is saying we may
prefer to be rich, but his argument has always pointed in a very different
direction, and he is as disturbed by greed and an attachment to wealth as much
as any other Stoic.
Seneca’s
discussion of money can be readily broadened to include any of the
circumstances of Fortune, and is not just about how much we possess, but also
about our relation to all of our external conditions. Vanity will encourage us
to define ourselves by Fortune, but it is also cowardly to neglect Fortune. The
key lies in treating Fortune rightly, never as an end, but always as an
indifferent means, always expecting it to come and go, and ordering all of our
efforts toward our only true end, wisdom and virtue alone.
My
thinking on priorities will profoundly alter the way I receive things, and the
way I give them away. Notice the humorous way the greedy man immediately thinks
he is worthy of being given something, because he can conceive of no other
purpose in the world.
Many
people also think that the appearance of their own character depends on how
much they give, and that they are seen to be doing it. But the quantities
involved, and the esteem gained by giving, are never the point. The captain of
industry is not better for giving millions of dollars than the minimum wage
worker who puts a single dollar in the collection box. The only thing that
could make them different is to whom they are giving, and why they are giving.
What do
I hope to see, so to speak, as the return for my investment? Am I giving to
increase my own position, or because it makes me feel satisfied with myself, or
in expectation of a favor in return? If my answer is expressed in terms of
other pieces of Fortune, this is not giving, but shuffling around those pieces
on the board of the marketplace. I am only bartering and trading one
circumstance for another.
But if
my answer is expressed in genuinely human terms, in terms of how my gifts of
Fortune can assist people to know the truth more fully and love the good more
deeply, then I am on the right track. I should try to give of myself so that
others can in turn be more fully themselves. The balance sheet of life is a
moral one, not a financial one, and I should give to people who are already
good, or who can be helped to become good.
Aristotle
argued that every virtue, guided by wisdom, is a mean between the extremes of
excess and deficiency. Generosity is by definition never selfish, and is also
never blind or thoughtless. It rests between stinginess and wastefulness, and
requires, as Seneca says, having an open pocket, but not a pocket with a hole.
The good man cannot help but give, because his acts of virtue are all that he
truly has, and he looks not to how much he spends, but how his spending helps
others to be better.
53. The
difficulties of giving
He who believes giving to be an easy
matter, is mistaken. It offers very great difficulties, if we bestow our bounty
rationally, and do not scatter it impulsively and at random.
I do this man a service, and I need a
good turn done me by that one. I help this other, because I pity him. This man,
again, I teach that he is not a fit object for poverty to hold down or degrade.
I shall not give some men anything,
although they are in want, because, even if I do give to them they will still
be in want. I shall proffer my bounty to some, and shall forcibly thrust it
upon others. I also cannot be neglecting my own interests while I am doing
this.
At no time do I make more people in my
debt than when I am giving things away. "What?" say you, "do you
give that you may receive again?" At any rate I do not give that I may
throw my bounty away. What I give should be so placed that although I cannot
ask for its return, yet it can be given back to me. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 24 (tr Stewart)
Back
when I was still in Boston, working in social services, one of the priests who
ran the agency was affectionately known for always being late in the morning.
This wasn’t because he was lazy, but because he was still one of those priests
who proudly wore his clerical collar, and this meant that he would be
constantly approached by the needy and homeless in the streets for assistance.
He took this duty seriously, and we would often not see him until the
afternoon.
His
method of offering help was, however, not what one might expect. If he was
asked for money to get food or clothes, he would never give money, but offered
to buy someone a meal, or provide him with new shoes and a coat.
This was
his way of estimating character. He knew that those who became angry with him
had other intentions in mind, but he would always encourage those who were
willing, and even those who appeared hesitant. He would often take someone to
breakfast, get to know him, and then suggest different options for finding
shelter, meals, medical assistance, and work. Many of these people became our
clients, and many became our friends.
The
priest gave in charity, because he gave all of himself, even as the lawyers and
bankers at the train stations looked the other way. He also realized that
giving to others must be reasonable and responsible, always keeping in mind not
just the act of giving, but how the gift would assist someone to be a better
human being.
Sometimes,
the people he met would be a bit dumbstruck, and awkwardly express that they
would always be in his debt. Again, his words were perhaps unusual.
“Yes,”
he would say, “You are in my debt. But you don’t need to give me anything. I hope that one day, however, when you
have more, you choose to give to
someone else, or maybe even to me, if you see me where you were just now.”
I think
he understood he had an interest in how his generosity was used, just as Seneca
did, and I know he was scolded for being selfish, just as Seneca was. “See! It
turns out you just want to get something in return!”
Of
course I have an interest, but it is not the interest of the greedy man. I
should not wish to be wasteful, but to see benefit from what has been shared.
For me, that benefit should be the knowledge that I have helped another to
practice virtue, that I would like to see him share for himself, and that I
would be glad if he also shared with me. I hope another man will act well
toward me, as I acted well toward him, but I can hardly ever force him to do so.
Love is a choice.
A bad
man expects repayment, but a good man is only grateful to receive it. A bad man
expects a return for his own profit, but a good man is happy to see the return
in the profit of another. A gift is only a gift when it is freely offered, and
never when it is demanded.
Seneca’s
adversary earlier accused him of wanting to be rich, and now accuses him of
wanting to be compensated. The response to the former also applies to the
latter. I should never desire or expect to be wealthy, though I may prefer it.
I should never desire or expect to be repaid, though I may prefer it.
Self-interest can simply be for the self to do what is good, while selfishness
is only to do what is good for the self.
54. A
field of freehandedness
. . . A benefit should be invested in
the same manner as a treasure buried deep in the earth, which you would not dig
up unless actually obliged.
Why, what opportunities of conferring
benefits the mere house of a rich man affords! For who considers generous behavior
due only to those who wear the toga? Nature bids me do good to mankind—what
difference does it make whether they be slaves or freemen, free-born or
emancipated, whether their freedom be legally acquired or bestowed by
arrangement among friends?
Wherever there is a human being, there is
an opportunity for a benefit. Consequently, money may be distributed even
within one's own threshold, and a field may be found there for the practice of
freehandedness, which is not so called because it is our duty towards free men,
but because it takes its rise in a freeborn mind.
In the case of the wise man, this never
falls upon base and unworthy recipients, and never becomes so exhausted as not,
whenever it finds a worthy object, to flow as if its store was undiminished. .
. .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 24 (tr Stewart)
Those
who are of the selfish sort treat any benefit simply as one half of an
exchange, and will constantly demand their payment, with interest. I learned
the hard way that friendship is often twisted into a transaction that continues
only as long as there is a profitable return. Those who are of the giving sort will
also invest, not for their own gain, but for the gain of others, and they seek
assistance only when in need.
Similarly,
he who lives by Fortune will only grant benefits to those who are fortunate,
those who wear the toga, because he wishes to share in their worldly
prosperity. The man who is poor, sick, or weak is of no interest to him. But he
who lives by Nature, by the merit of his own good deeds alone, has a much wider
field to work in, because each and every person is an opportunity for giving
benefit. Any man, whatever his position or circumstance, is of interest and
concern to him.
The
concepts of benefit, favor, or patronage only take on sinister tones in the
hands of sinister folks. I remember someone in Boston who was in principle a
Republican, but would only contribute money to campaigns by Democrats. This was
because the Republicans were rarely elected in that state, and they could
hardly provide a civil service promotion in return for the support. That is how
favors, and politics, get a bad name.
No,
those worthy of a benefit are all of those who will employ it to improve their
own character, rich or poor, healthy or sick, powerful or weak, though it will
be most needed by those who are poor, sick, or weak. Its return is measured by
how an act of charity will permit others the means for further acts of charity,
and there is wisdom to the old saying that kindness should always be passed on.
It may even return back to its source.
What
Seneca calls freehandedness is not free because it is only given to other free
men, but because it comes from the conviction of someone who is free in his own
thinking, who is his own master, and therefore not bound like a slave to the service
of his circumstances.
The good
man will sow freely in his field, though he is a fool to sow on barren ground. He
farms not merely for his profit, but to feed people, friends and strangers
alike.
55. The
student and the master
. . . You have, therefore, no grounds
for misunderstanding the honorable, brave, and spirited language that you hear
from those who are studying wisdom, and first of all observe this, that a
student of wisdom is not the same thing as a man who has made himself perfect
in wisdom.
The former will say to you, "In my
talk I express the most admirable sentiments, yet I am still weltering amid
countless ills. You must not force me to act up to my rules; at the present
time I am forming myself, molding my character, and striving to rise myself to
the height of a great example. If I should ever succeed in carrying out all
that I have set myself to accomplish, you may then demand that my words and
deeds should correspond."
But he who has reached the summit of
human perfection will deal otherwise with you, and will say, "In the first
place, you have no business to allow yourself to sit in judgment upon your
betters."
I have already obtained one proof of my
righteousness, in having become an object of dislike to bad men. However, to give
you a rational answer, which I grudge to no man, listen to what I declare, and
at what price I value all things.
Riches, I say, are not a good thing,
for if they were, they would make men good. Now since that which is found even among
bad men cannot be termed good, I do not allow them to be called so.
Nevertheless, I admit that they are
desirable and useful and contribute great comforts to our lives.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 24 (tr Stewart)
Those
who despise a life measured by virtue will immediately condemn those of us who
struggle to live well. They will attack our weakness, and not the strength of
what we seek. They will tell us how often we fail, while ignoring the very
thing we are working toward. They revel in our imperfection, even as we try to
make ourselves better.
To say
that the goal cannot be achieved because I have not yet achieved it is much
like saying that a journey is pointless because it has not yet been completed.
Do not be deceived. Those who discourage you from what is true and good in life
do so precisely because they are convinced that the things they possess define
them. They mock you because they think life is about wealth and recognition,
they degrade you because they think that life is about power and influence, and
they mistreat you because they think that life is about conflict and conquest.
They are
misguided, because they assume that wealth or power are themselves good things,
failing to see that they can only become good when directed by wisdom and
virtue. Money can be very harmful, since it can be abused, but virtue is always
beneficial, since it always gives right purpose to what is used.
Do not
fight on their terms. Love them, and teach them what is right, in word and by
example. You will often think that you have failed, but you have already succeeded
within yourself just by acting with charity in the face of hatred.
I have
absolutely no right to consider myself better than any other man, because I am
not yet a good man. I hope and pray that I may one day be so. In the meantime,
I would prefer assistance to rejection. I am learning, step by painful step, to
extract myself from the illusion that being rich in the world will make me good
in my soul.
Yet I
have known others who are indeed wise and good, and they are priceless examples
to follow. I have often found such people in the most unlikely of places. They
are rarely recognized for what they are, because most of us are still working
from a clouded perspective on life. You will see no glamor, no sales pitch, and
no vanity. You will see only a humble and faithful commitment to character. You
will see someone who cares about you for your sake, and nothing more.
Don’t
condemn the student because he is not yet a master. The student is striving to
be a master, simply by learning to rule himself. The student will know he has
become a master when he sees everything through the eyes of Nature, not through
the demands of Fortune. Then he may rightly say that he is better.
56. No
unlucky days
Learn, then, since we both agree that riches
are desirable, what my reason is for counting them among good things, and in
what respects I should behave differently to you if I possessed them.
Place me as master in the house of a
very rich man. Place me where gold and silver plate is used for the commonest
purposes. I shall not think more of myself because of things, which even though
they are in my house, they are yet not a part of me.
Take me away to the wooden bridge and
put me down there among the beggars. I shall not despise myself because I am
sitting among those who hold out their hands for alms. For what can the lack of
a piece of bread matter to one who does not lack the power of dying?
Well, then? I prefer the magnificent
house to the beggar's bridge. Place me among magnificent furniture and all the
appliances of luxury. I shall not think myself any happier because my cloak is
soft, because my guests rest upon purple.
Change the scene. I shall be no more
miserable if my weary head rests upon a bundle of hay, or if I lie upon a
cushion from the circus, with all the stuffing on the point of coming out
through its patches of threadbare cloth.
Well, then? I prefer, as far as my feelings
go, to show myself in public dressed in woolen and in robes of office, rather
than with naked or half-covered shoulders. I should like every day's business
to turn out just as I wish it to do, and new congratulations to be constantly
following upon the former ones.
Yet I will not pride myself upon this.
Change all this good fortune for its opposite, let my spirit be distracted by
losses, grief, various kinds of attacks. Let no hour pass without some dispute.
I shall not on this account, though beset by the greatest miseries, call myself
the most miserable of beings, nor shall I curse any particular day, for I have
taken care to have no unlucky days. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 25 (tr Stewart)
I must
admit that I sometimes feel baffled by Seneca on virtue and fortune. I know
that I must be indifferent to wealth, but I also know that I may prefer it, and
it seems strange that I can both despise and desire one and the same thing. It
isn’t just the terminology that can get in the way, but a sense that the entire
process of moral judgment is a precarious balancing act between conscience and
convenience.
I then
recognize, however, that this appearance of tension arises only because I am
still confused about the nature of what is valuable. Virtue and fortune do not
differ in their degree, but they are rather completely different in kind, and
if I think that I’m doing well by caring more about my character, and bit less
about my possessions, I’m actually well off the mark. I should rather care only
for my character, and nothing at all for my possessions. Now my circumstances
will become useful or preferable only
if they can assist my practice of virtue, and it is my proper use of them that
will give them any value. The means must be totally subservient to the end.
My
feelings may prefer wealth to poverty, or ease to difficulty, but this should
in no way affect my happiness, which relies exclusively upon my own actions. If
I believe I am slightly happier because I have a good job, or slightly more
miserable because I am sick, then I misunderstand what it means to be happy,
and I am mixing up preference and principle.
My
happiness will depend upon whether I care about the right things. This revolves
around understanding that my nature is defined by what I do, not by what
happens to me. As soon as I can grasp this, I will no longer worry about my
fortune for its own sake, and I will no longer try balancing conscience and
convenience. I will hardly be miserable if I lose something that doesn’t matter
to me.
For most
of us, trying to give value to both virtue and circumstance results in an
unfitting compromise, and quite often means the surrender of the former to the
latter. There no can be no half measures. Stoic self-reliance will only seem
heartless if our hearts are in the wrong place, and continue to love the wrong
things.
I can
then begin to realize that no circumstance is in itself good or bad, unless I
make it so, and that no day is lucky or unlucky, because luck does not
determine me, but rather I determine what I will do with luck. The Universe is
hardly random, of course, since everything in Nature is in its place for a
purpose, and what we call luck is really only in our perception. I will learn
to see that any luck, any circumstance, whether or not I may prefer it, is
always an opportunity for benefit. Not all luck will increase my fortune, but
it can always be a means to improve my character.
57. A Conqueror
or a captive?
. . . What, then, is the upshot of all
this? It is that I prefer to have to regulate joys than to stifle sorrows. The
great Socrates would say the same thing to you.
"Make me," he would say, "the
conqueror of all nations. Let the voluptuous car of Bacchus bear me in triumph
to Thebes from the rising of the sun. Let the kings of the Persians receive
laws from me. Yet I shall still feel myself to be a man even at the very moment
when all around salute me as a god.
“Straightway, connect this lofty height
with a headlong fall into misfortune. Let me be placed upon a foreign chariot
that I may grace the triumph of a proud and savage conqueror. I will follow
another's car with no more humility than I showed when I stood in my own.”
What then? In spite of all this, I would
rather be a conqueror than a captive. I despise the whole dominion of Fortune,
but still, if I were given my choice, I would choose its better parts. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 25 (tr Stewart)
I would
indeed gladly choose pleasure over pain, comfort over suffering, but I can only
free myself from slavery to preferences when I begin to see that all of my
circumstances should be in the service of right action. Give me what is easier,
but I should be just as willing, and just as proud, to face what is harder.
I have
long been in awe and wonder at the Gospel scene of the Agony in the Garden. I
imagine people of many faiths and cultures can surely appreciate both the pain
and difficulty of such a decision, as well as the love and humility of the
choice that was made. From Matthew 26:36-39:
Then
Jesus went with them to a place called Gethsemane, and he said to his
disciples, “Sit here, while I go yonder and pray.” And taking with him Peter
and the two sons of Zebedee, he began to be sorrowful and troubled. Then he
said to them, “My soul is very sorrowful, even to death; remain here, and watch
with me.” And going a little farther he fell on his face and prayed, “My
Father, if it be possible, let this cup pass from me; nevertheless, not as I
will, but as thou wilt.”
My own struggles
have never been about the redemption of humanity, but they have been hard
enough to bear. I made poor choices about attachments, and paid many years of
consequences for them. They were life-defining mistakes. I often wish none of
it had ever happened, but I then also realize that the pain was what led to the
only things that are now good within me. Give me contentment over loss, but not
at the expense of my soul.
As much
as I might like to be driving the chariot of a conquering king, can I still
learn to be a decent and happy man if I am paraded about as a vanquished
captive? Can I be humble and righteous both in victory and in defeat?
Kipling
always said it so well:
If you can meet with Triumph and
Disaster
And treat those two impostors just the
same. . .
58. Spurs
and curbs
. . . I shall make whatever befalls me
become a good thing, but I prefer that what befalls me should be comfortable
and pleasant, and unlikely to cause me annoyance. For you need not suppose that
any virtue exists without labor, but some virtues need spurs, while others need
the curb.
As we have to check our body on a
downward path, and to urge it to climb a steep one, so also the path of some
virtues leads downhill, that of others uphill.
Can we doubt that patience, courage,
constancy, and all the other virtues that have to meet strong opposition, and
to trample Fortune under their feet, are climbing, struggling, and winning their
way up a steep ascent?
Why! Is it not equally evident that
generosity, moderation, and gentleness glide easily downhill? With the latter
we must hold in our spirit, lest it run away with us, with the former we must
urge and spur it on.
We ought, therefore, to apply these
energetic, combative virtues to poverty, and to riches those other more thrifty
ones that trip lightly along, and merely support their own weight. This being
the distinction between them, I would rather have to deal with those that I can
practice in comparative quiet, than those that can only be a trial trial
through blood and sweat.
"Wherefore," says the sage,
"I do not talk one way and live another, but you do not rightly understand
what I say. The sound of my words alone reaches your ears, but you do not try
to find out their meaning."
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 25 (tr Stewart)
Sometimes
I need to push myself forward, and sometimes I need to hold myself back. Virtue
always consists in the mean or balance between too little and too much, and
will therefore need either drive or restraint to find the mark.
I
understand Seneca’s point immediately, because it is a common pattern. Just as
it is easier to go downhill than it is to go uphill, there is less effort in withholding
force than applying more. Now some virtues demand that we drive ourselves on,
and others that we rein ourselves in. Fortitude, for example, requires that we
push forward, while temperance requires that we pull back.
This can
also apply to having greater or lesser gifts of fortune. Having more and
spending less is a far easier thing than having less and acquiring more. A
preference for the former should make perfect sense.
Here I
confront a difficulty, though it has far less to do with the truth of Seneca’s
general observation that the quirks of my own temperament. Aristotle argued
that while the mean of virtue tends to be similar for all of us, the mean for a
certain individual might rest in a rather different place, depending on
disposition or habit. If I am already a forceful person, fortitude may require
me to curb myself from recklessness rather than spur myself out of cowardice.
If I am already satisfied with too little, temperance may require me to spur
myself out of self-denial rather than curb myself from gluttony.
Now
Seneca has repeatedly argued that wealth is preferable to poverty, because it
is better to work with more than with less, and as a rule he is quite right.
Yet I have found that my personal tendencies often seem to work in the opposite
way. This isn’t because Seneca has it backwards, because, as Aristotle said,
there will be exceptions on both sides of what is most common. I suspect I’m
the one who has it a bit backwards.
I regularly
find it harder to restrain myself from excess and easier to drive myself out of
deficiency. When more is given to me, I usually make less of it, and when less
is given to me, I have better success at making more of it. This hardly means I
enjoy having less, but I meet a far greater resistance when I have more.
Some
horses are easier to rein in and other horses are easier to drive on. I am that
second kind of horse. I am happier with the wind in my face than at my back.
Perhaps
if someone is already bit more practiced in virtue, someone like a Seneca, pulling
back is easier than pushing forward. I am still a beginner, and work best when
I struggle through something. Hopefully when I have found my right balance, I
can start coasting instead of climbing. Right now, I will tend to fall flat on
my face when I go downhill.
59. Prepared
for the siege
"What difference, then, is there
between me, who is a fool, and you, who are a wise man?"
All the difference in the world: for
riches are slaves in the house of a wise man, but masters in that of a fool.
You accustom yourself to them and cling to them as if somebody had promised
that they should be yours forever, but a wise man never thinks so much about
poverty as when he is surrounded by riches.
No general ever trusts so implicitly in
the maintenance of peace as not to make himself ready for a war, which, though
it may not actually be waged, has nevertheless been declared. You are rendered
over-proud by a fine house, as though it could never be burned or fall down,
and your heads are turned by riches as though they were beyond the reach of all
dangers and were so great that Fortune has not sufficient strength to swallow
them up.
You sit idly playing with your wealth
and do not foresee the perils in store for it, as savages generally do when
besieged, for, not understanding the use of siege artillery, they look on idly
at the labors of the besiegers and do not understand the object of the machines
which they are putting together at a distance.
And this is exactly what happens to
you. You go to sleep over your property, and never reflect how many misfortunes
loom menacingly around you on all sides, and soon will plunder you of costly
spoils, but if one takes away riches from the wise man, one leaves him still in
possession of all that is his: for he lives happy in the present, and without
fear for the future. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 26 (tr Stewart)
Seneca
has explained that fortune, which expands to include our money, power, and fame,
will hardly define who we are, though our attitude toward fortune will make all
the difference. The wise man never lets himself be entrapped by his
surroundings, but depends only on the merits of his own thoughts and actions. It
is when we attach ourselves to things, when we desire to form ourselves by what
is outside of us, that we become fools.
The wise
man has long prepared himself for the loss of any of his fortune, because its
absence will make him no different than he already is. The fool thinks of
nothing else, and so cannot even imagine himself separated from his position
and his belongings.
I have
known many people who are the fools Seneca describes, and at times I have been
one of them myself. Having dedicated everything they are to their worldly
achievements, there is nothing left underneath the layers of acquisitions, no
self-reliance, no convictions, and no integrity. I have often thought of it
like people who cannot conceive of their own appearance without cosmetics or
fine clothes, and who would never leave home without such vain trappings.
The
military analogy is an appropriate one, for the fool does not even recognize
the enemy at all, and he has no idea what power is arrayed against him. He is
weak and unprepared, because he will not know how to confront his emptiness
when fortune, the foe he once assumed was always a friend, turns on him.
The
lover of fortune may tell himself that he is secure, since he will make certain
to always keep a hold of what he says he possesses. He cannot assure this, of
course, because he is already a slave to his circumstances, and he has never really
acquired anything at all, but let us, for the sake of argument, say that he
manages to be rich, powerful, and praised for his whole life. Has he not now
come out on top? As we used to say in the 1980’s, he who dies with the most
toys wins.
What he
does not understand is that the damage will not be done after he loses his fortune,
but it was done long before, when he entered into her bondage. It may only
become clear to him much later that he surrendered responsibility for himself
the moment he sold his virtue for riches. Like any Faustian bargain, the true
cost was tragically overlooked.
The
outcome of the siege was decided well before it began, by whether I was
prepared or unprepared to defend the content of my character.
60. Principles
and prejudices
. . . The great Socrates, or anyone
else who had the same superiority to and power to withstand the things of this
life, would say, “I have no more fixed principle than that of not altering the
course of my life to suit your prejudices. You may pour your accustomed talk
upon me from all sides. I shall not think that you are abusing me, but that you
are merely wailing like poor little infants.”
This is what the man will say who
possesses wisdom, whose mind, being free from vices, bids him to reproach
others, not because he hates them, but in order to improve them.
And to this he will add, "Your
opinion of me affects me with pain, not for my own sake but for yours, because
to hate perfection and to assail virtue is in itself a resignation of all hope
of doing well. You do me no harm; neither do men harm the gods when they
overthrow their altars. But it is clear that your intention is an evil one and
that you will wish to do harm even where you are not able.
“I bear with your prating in the same
spirit in which Jupiter, best and greatest, bears with the idle tales of the
poets, one of whom represents him with wings, another with horns, another as an
adulterer staying out all night, another as dealing harshly with the gods,
another as unjust to men, another as the seducer of noble youths whom he
carries off by force, and those, too, his own relatives, another as a parricide
and the conqueror of another's kingdom, and that of his father's.”
The only result of such tales is that
men feel less shame at committing sin if they believe the gods to be guilty of
such actions. . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life, Chapter
26 (tr Stewart)
A life
dedicated to pleasure and position, which is of necessity a life that is also
subservient to what is outside of us, will be a life of conformity. Once I
begin, in even the most cursory manner, to think in terms of Nature instead of
Fortune, it becomes apparent how often principle gives way to prejudice. Instead
of asking how to do something in a way that is right, we assume something is
right because of the way it is already done. The surrender to fashion means the
surrender of reason, and it will immediately dismiss what is uncommon and
unpopular.
To
borrow a modern phrase, don’t take it personally. Some people will try to
ridicule anything that is different from their established orthodoxy, and
degrading others is the only way they know to make themselves feel better.
Their ignorance and malice does not have to become my ignorance and malice.
For some,
a correction or a rebuke can only be an insult. I, however, can choose to help,
not to harm, and to allow myself to be helped in turn, not to feel resentment.
I can let an argument be weighed by what is sound, not by what is preferred.
I know I
am starting down the right path when the pain I feel no longer comes from my
own loss, but from the loss of others. Socrates once said that a better man can
not be harmed by a worse man, because even as the worse man increases his own
vice, he can never take away the virtue of a better man. I should worry less
about how others are vainly trying to hurt me, and far more about helping them
not to hurt themselves.
Some
will try to blame what is Divine, however it may be understood, for their own
weaknesses. If they only reflected upon this clearly for a moment, they would
understand that the Divine is, by its very definition, that which is perfect
and lacking in nothing, the source by which all other things become good. God
cannot be hurt by insult or abuse, and whenever we reject God to excuse
ourselves from accountability we only insult or abuse ourselves.
In like
manner, the man who seeks to be god-like, for all of his flaws, does not need
to fear the malice of others. He should continually improve himself, and wish
to see others transform their own hatred into love.
61. Silence
over show
. . . But although this conduct of
yours does not hurt me, yet, for your own sake, I advise you, respect virtue.
Believe those who having long followed her call, that what they follow is a
thing of might, and daily appears mightier.
Reverence her as you would the gods,
and reverence her followers as you would the priests of the gods, and whenever
any mention of sacred writings is made, favor us with your tongues. Favor is
not derived, as most people imagine, from applause, but commands silence, so that
divine service may be performed without being interrupted by any words of evil
omen. It is much more necessary that you should be ordered to do this so that
whenever utterance is made by that oracle, you may listen to it with attention
and in silence.
Whenever anyone beats a sistrum,
pretending to do so by divine command, anyone proficient in grazing his own
skin covers his arms and shoulders with blood from light cuts, anyone crawls on
his knees howling along the street, or any old man clad in linen comes forth in
daylight with a lamp and laurel branch and cries out that one of the gods is
angry, you crowd round him and listen to his words, and each increases the
other's dumb amazement by declaring him to be divinely inspired!
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 26 (tr Stewart)
There
are times for making a joyful sound, but I have always thought that respect is
best practiced in silence. This is not just a question of good manners, but
rather an expression of humility in the face of what we hold dear. If I am full
of sound and fury, I hear only my own words, and I draw attention only to my
own spectacle. I am hardly pointing to what is greater than myself, and I am
only trying to make myself greater. I am unable to listen over my own noise.
Virtue
is worthy of reverence, because it is the path to our happiness. Virtue is also
divine, not only in a poetic sense, but by participating in the unity of all
that is good. Man improves himself through his own judgment and action, by so
doing he plays his special part in the perfection of the whole of Nature, and
thereby he shows his reverence to Providence.
We will
recognize those who seek virtue by the way they empty themselves of all
diversion, just as we will recognize those who shun virtue by the way they fill
themselves with vanity. Part of my daily struggle is to listen more than I
speak, to give more than I receive, and to show respect instead of demanding
it.
Making a
show of things can so easily become an act of arrogance. When I was in college,
I remember that far too many of the students in the Honors Program were less
interested in learning, and more interested in constantly speaking about how
much they already knew. When I went to work, I saw the domination of those
gifted at glorifying themselves. When I have tried to worship, I see far more
performance than I do piety.
I have
already wasted too much of my life deluded by appearances, and neglecting the
improvement of my own heart and mind. I thought for too long that beautiful
things, things worthy of admiration, had to be exciting to the senses and
enticing to the passions. I was ignoring that a person is beautiful because of
character, not because of display.
Practicing
the art of silent reverence can be quite demanding in a world so full of flashy
images, constantly telling us to pose and consume, but I find more and more
that I can’t love virtue if I am distracted by mere impressions.
62. A
trial of strength
Behold! From that prison of his, which
by entering he cleansed from shame and rendered more honorable than any senate
house, Socrates addresses you, saying:
“What is this madness of yours? What is
this disposition, at war alike with gods and men, which leads you to defame
virtue and to outrage holiness with malicious accusations? Praise good men, if
you are able. If not, pass them by in silence. If indeed you take pleasure in
this offensive abusiveness, fall foul of one another, for when you rave against
Heaven, I do not say that you commit sacrilege, but you waste your time.
“I once afforded Aristophanes with the
subject of a jest, and since then all the crew of comic poets have made me a
mark for their venomous wit. My virtue has been made to shine more brightly by
the very blows which have been aimed at it, for it is to its advantage to be
brought before the public and exposed to temptation, nor do any people
understand its greatness more than those who by their assaults have made trial
of its strength.
“The hardness of flint is known to none
so well as to those who strike it. I offer myself to all attacks, like some
lonely rock in a shallow sea, which the waves never cease to beat upon from
whatever quarter they may come, but which they cannot thereby move from its
place, nor yet wear away, for however many years they may unceasingly dash
against it.
“Leap upon me, rush upon me, I will
overcome you by enduring your onset. Whatever strikes against that which is firm
and unconquerable merely injures itself by its own violence. Therefore, seek
some soft and yielding object to pierce with your darts.” . . .
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 27 (tr Stewart)
I have
often felt very weak, because I have never been terribly good at defeating
others, either in mind or in body. I am quite wrong to think this, however,
since having power over others is hardly strength at all. Strength is actually
in having power over oneself.
I once
read a newspaper article about someone I had known in my younger days, who was
quoted as saying: “I pursue every opportunity, and I take what I want.” This
saddened me, because I expected better. Success is not in taking what I want,
but in wanting to give so I can be better. Conquest is hardly the pursuit of a
noble opportunity.
My
feelings have always bruised far too easily, so I also thought I would not even
be any good at ruling myself. My mistake was that I assumed being strong
required hardening my emotions, or disposing of them entirely. I have seen many
people I cared for do precisely that, and they became convinced they were
strong because they were now cold and heartless.
No, it
isn’t about not feeling, or not caring. It isn’t about stifling my emotions,
but rather about allowing my reason to make the best use of those emotions. Socrates
was attacked and abused over and over, and I have no doubt that he must have
felt pain. What he managed to do was to take the offense, and to transform the
attempt to harm him into a means for building his virtue.
I will
only succumb to the feelings of being rejected or dismissed if I allow them to
rule me. Throw an obstacle in the way of my judgment and choice, and yes, it
will cause be pain, but it need not cause me harm. Like a muscle that is
strengthened through repeated exercise, you only give me the chance to become
stronger in my convictions. By doing wrong, you give me more opportunity to do
right. If you must tempt me to be angry, or to strike back in return, I can
decide all the more to love instead of hate. You have made yourself weaker, and
helped me to be stronger, by foolishly trying to destroy me.
Can a
bully steal my lunch money, can a friend abandon me, can a lawyer leave me
penniless, and can a tyrant take my life? Of course, but those aren’t the
things that matter. Socrates was not weak in prison because he lost his case,
but rather he was strong in prison because his spirit was unconquerable.
63. Pimples
and ulcers
. . . But have you leisure to peer into
other men's evil deeds and to sit in judgment upon anybody? To ask how it is
that this philosopher has so roomy a house, or that one has so good a dinner?
Do you look at other people's pimples while yon yourselves are covered with
countless ulcers? This is as though one who was eaten up by the mange were to
point with scorn at the moles and warts on the bodies of the handsomest men.
Reproach Plato with having sought for
money, reproach Aristotle with having obtained it, Democritus with having
disregarded it, Epicurus with having spent it. Cast Phaedrus and Alcibiades in
my own teeth, you who reach the height of enjoyment whenever you get an
opportunity of imitating our vices!
Why do you not rather cast your eyes around
yourselves at the ills that tear you to pieces on every side, some attacking
you from without, some burning in your own chests? However little you know your
own place, mankind has not yet come to such a place that you can have leisure
to wag your tongues to the reproach of your betters.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 27 (tr Stewart)
It often
seems so easy to diminish others and to elevate ourselves, perhaps because we
think the diminishing is the very means for the elevating. I know this not
simply from observing others, but from being brutally honest about myself.
We
rarely recognize our own hypocrisy, because we ignorantly but genuinely work
from the premise that there are indeed different rules for ourselves and for
others. We might feel ashamed to say this to others, but we hardly feel guilty
about thinking it to ourselves.
If I
have already begun by thinking that my own satisfaction is the measure of all
things, I will never recognize myself in others, or be called to serve them,
but I will rather see them only as a means to my own end. You must make
yourself better, but I was already good to begin with. The pimple on your face
is obviously an outrage, even as the ulcer on my own is actually quite
handsome, thank you.
I can
only overcome such a contradiction of character if I grasp the role of human nature
within all of Nature. My own humanity, as a being made to know the truth and to
love what is good, is never inherently in conflict with the humanity of others,
which, for all of our different circumstances, is essentially the same as mine.
I will
only cure myself when I look at another, and I see myself. I can only love when
I am willing to humbly give of myself for others. I can only be just if I am
able to offer respect no differently than I ask it to be given.
We often
hear that we should not judge, but I suggest that we must rightly distinguish.
To make a judgment is to determine the true from the false, and to make a
judgment more specifically about morals is to determine the right from the
wrong. Remove these, and you remove the very guides that inform all human
actions. Relativism is an unintelligible excuse for neglecting objective accountability.
Instead,
we abuse judgment when we pursue it with a double standard, and when we pursue
it with malice. By all means, judge the good from the bad, but do not judge
others any differently than you judge yourself. By all means, separate right
from wrong, but do not correct others to make them look worse, but so that you might
help them to become better. There is a world of difference between the man who
judges with condemnation and the man who judges with compassion.
Above
all else, I must never consider my responsibility for another before I have
mastered my responsibility for myself. Specks in the eye or the temptations of
adultery can certainly be harmful things, but they are hardly as harmful as
when I expect others to do what I won’t do for myself.
64. A
lofty standpoint
This you do not understand, and you
bear a countenance that does not befit your condition, like many men who sit in
the circus or the theater without having learned that their home is already in
mourning.
But I, looking forward from a lofty
standpoint, can see what storms are either threatening you, and will burst in
torrents upon you somewhat later, or are close upon you and on the point of
sweeping away all that you possess.
Why, though you are hardly aware of it,
is there not a whirling hurricane at this moment spinning round and confusing
your minds, making them seek and avoid the very same things, now raising them
aloft and now dashing them below?
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 28 (tr Stewart)
The text
of Seneca the Younger’s On the happy life
abruptly ends here. I don’t know if the later sections were lost over the
centuries, or if Seneca never finished them. I would certainly have liked to
read more, but what has been given is already far more than enough. The
philosopher has reminded me in so many ways to look at everything from a lofty
standpoint, not with any sense of superiority, but with a broader perspective
on how I should understand my own human condition in right relation to all
other things.
If I
view myself only narrowly, from the immediate confines of my fortune and
amusements, I will never understand who I really am, why I am here, and what I
have to live for. I will never grasp how much I have wasted, how I have harmed
myself and done wrong to others, and how close I now am to having abandoned all
of my blessings. I will be confused about what to love, and so I will pursue
all the wrong things, and neglect all the right things. I will want what is bad
for me, and therefore I will both crave it and curse it. I will just be
throwing myself around blindly if I cannot distinguish between what is reliable
and what is unreliable.
Yet if I
seek the higher ground, and look at everything from above, what appeared jumbled
and confounding will now reveal meaning and purpose. I will learn that I am not
determined by my circumstances, but by the character of my own choices and actions.
I will recognize that nothing external to me is good or bad unless I choose to
make it so, and that every situation is an opportunity for becoming better. I
will not replace a love for what is greater with a preference for what is
lesser. I will embrace Nature as the measure of all that is good, and respect
the place of all these things in the harmony of Providence.
I may
have wanted to read more of Seneca’s book, but I don’t need to. So too in my
own life, I may have wanted more time and more chances, but I don’t need them.
What has been given is already far more than enough. I am very much mistaken if
I think that living any longer, with more possessions, power, or recognition,
will give me a better life. By all means, pass such things my way, but only my
good use of them will make any difference at all. Even the briefest, simplest,
most humble, and most unassuming life is sufficient to live with excellence.
The good can die young, poor, and forgotten, because the good never need to
become old, rich, and renowned.
I have
been a teacher, a counselor, a bartender, a writer, and a quite reliable gofer,
and sometimes I was even paid for it.
I have
played music with an orchestra in a fancy concert hall, and with an Irish folk
band behind chicken wire in the best dive bar in town.
I have
paid for a new car in cash, and swept the house for loose change to buy lunch.
I
bungled my way to a doctorate, and even became a questionably ordained minister.
I display the diploma for the latter, but not for the former.
I
wandered remote mountains in perfect contentment without seeing another soul
for days, and I wandered the streets of big cities feeling completely alone
surrounded by millions.
I have
stood up to bullies and demagogues, and I have almost always lost the battles
on their terms, but I have almost always won them on mine.
I have
drunk the finest single malt from crystal, and rotgut from a paper bag. I
learned that neither made me a better man, and often made me a worse one.
I briefly
met Mother Teresa, and she spoke only a very few words to me that changed my
life. I later met a murderer when I was working in prison ministry, who added a
few more words that changed my life even more.
I have
dug myself into the darkest holes, and grappled my way back up into warm
sunlight. I have fallen down far too many times to count, but to this day I
have always gotten back on my feet, however much the worse for wear.
Through
it all, I became used to the Black Dog always nipping at my heels.
The most
selfish person I ever knew broke my heart, and the most compassionate person I
ever knew tried to help me mend it.
I lost a
child, and I tried to raise two more. I have no idea what will become of them,
but I hope that they will always think for themselves, and that they will never
lose their sense of what is good and beautiful.
Those
were all quite wonderful, and sometimes even extraordinary, things to have. I
am grateful for them, but I never needed them. I will welcome it if
circumstance offers something else, but it would only be an encore. I don’t
need more, I only need to make right of what I already am.
All I
ever need to be happy is to make a decision, at any given moment, to depend
upon the virtue of what I do, not upon what is done to me. Any kind of moment
will suffice to do well.
No comments:
Post a Comment