. . . Marcus Cato, when he was praising
Curius and Coruncanius and that century in which the possession of a few small
silver coins was an offence which was punished by the Censor, himself owned four
million sesterces; a less fortune, no doubt, than that of Crassus, but larger
than of Cato the Censor.
If the amounts be compared, he had
outstripped his great-grandfather further than he himself was outdone by
Crassus, and if still greater riches had fallen to his lot, he would not have
spurned them, for the wise man does not think himself unworthy of any chance
presents.
He does not love riches, but he prefers
to have them. He does not receive them into his spirit, but only into his
house, nor does he cast away from him what he already possesses, but keeps
them, and is willing that his virtue should receive a larger subject matter for
its exercise.
—Seneca
the Younger, On the happy life,
Chapter 21 (tr Stewart)
I can
hardly make any profound judgments about Roman politics, and I am ignorant of
all the subtleties of Seneca’s own political thinking. These references,
however, are surely intended to ask the reader to consider the difference
between good men who happen to be rich, and bad men who love being rich.
Cato the
Younger, and his great-grandfather Cato the Elder, were both very wealthy men,
but Seneca admired both of them greatly for their character. It is interesting
that Cato the Younger praised Manius Curius Dentatus, a consul of the third
century BC who was known for his great frugality, and who, legend tells us,
once said he preferred eating his turnips to receiving political bribes,
because he thought it better to rule rich men than be one himself.
There seems
quite a difference between the prosperous Cato and the thrifty Curius, but I
suggest that we are meant to see that this hardly matters. Curius wasn’t good
because he was poor, and Cato wasn’t bad because he was rich. They were both
good men because they pursued virtue, regardless of how much they possessed.
No, the
real contrast is between Cato and his contemporary, Crassus. While both men
were rich, though Crassus was apparently richer, the similarity ends there.
Cato, a follower of Stoicism, stood for the values of the Roman Republic
against the First Triumvirate of Caesar, Pompey, and Crassus. Seneca viewed
Cato as a man of moral principle, but Crassus was the Roman equivalent of a modern
real estate mogul, who mixed his desire for personal profit with political
power plays.
Cato and
Crassus were similar in their circumstances, but radically different in their
priorities. We have all seen the difference between those who use their wealth
to serve others, and those who use others to serve their wealth.
A wise
man does not love money, and he does not seek it for its own sake, though he
may well choose to prefer it. This may well seem like a petty distinction of
semantics, and we can use whatever terminology we like, but there is a real and
critical difference between want and preference. The Stoic should want only
virtue, and avoid only vice. He should be indifferent to all other things, and
make use of them insofar as they help him to be virtuous and not vicious.
Accordingly, I should only want to be a good man, not a rich man, or a powerful
man, or a popular man.
But let
us say all things are equal, and I could be a good man whether I was rich or
poor. I will take either circumstance, but I would most likely prefer the
option of wealth over poverty, health over sickness, a long life over a short
life, many friends over no friends. These are all certainly more pleasant, and
they might appear to offer me greater opportunities. Where a condition does not
conflict with virtue, I will rightly have the free choice of a preference, but
any preference must always be relative to and defer to virtue.
My own
silly way of remembering this is that I can take it or leave it, but if I don’t
have to leave it, I’ll gladly take it.
I
propose that Curius was a virtuous man who preferred
poverty, and Cato was a virtuous man who preferred
wealth, while Cassius was a vicious man who wanted
wealth. It all reduces to whether I love something external for itself, or if I
love virtue and also welcome something external.
My own
experience is that the absence of fortune may actually be preferable to the
presence of fortune far more often than we think, and in this regard I am drawn
more to Curius. I find I usually prefer turnips to the burden of wealth. But
that is a reflection for another time.
Written in 8/1995
Image: Jacopo Amigoni, Marcus Curius Dentatus Refuses the Gifts of the Samnites (c. 1736)
Note the turnips by the fire.
No comments:
Post a Comment