.
. . “Yes, but nothing can be more beautiful than this too which reason would
have us add to what we have agreed upon.”
“What
is that?” I asked.
“Happiness
seems to include many things: do all these join it together as into a whole
which is happiness, as though each thing were a different part thereof, or is
any one of them a good which fulfills the essence of happiness, and do the
others merely bear relations to this one?''
“I
would have you make this plain by the enunciation of these particulars.”
“Do
we not,” she asked, “hold that happiness is a good thing?”
“Yes,”
I answered, “the highest good.”
“But
you may apply this quality of happiness to them all. For the perfect satisfaction
is the same, and the highest power, and veneration, and renown, and pleasure;
these are all held to be happiness.”
“What
then?” I asked.
“Are
all these things, satisfaction, power, and the others, as it were, members of
the body, happiness, or do they all bear their relation to the good, as members
to a head?”
“I
understand what you propose to examine, but I am waiting eagerly to hear what
you will lay down.”
“I
would have you take the following explanation,” she said. “If these were all members
of the one body, happiness, they would differ individually. For this is the nature
of particulars, to make up one body of different parts.
“But
all these have been shown to be one and the same. Therefore they are not as
members; and further, this happiness will then appear to be joined together
into a whole body out of one member, which is impossible. “
“That
is quite certain,” said I, “but I would hear what is to come.” . . .
—from
Book 3, Prose 10
No good
thing ever comes easily, they always told, me, and if philosophy is indeed a
good thing, philosophy will hardly come easily either. Perhaps it will even
come the hardest of all, because it concerns itself with not just any good, but
with the greatest good.
This is
not an easy section of the text. In theory, it is about the relationship of
universals and particulars, between what is common to the whole on the one
hand, and specific to the parts on the other.
In
practice, it asks us to really consider whether being happy comes from adding
up certain individual things, or whether all the individual things are only
expressions of one and the same happiness.
That
didn’t necessarily help, did it? I am sympathetic, because the only time I had
it explained to me in a classroom, the esteemed professor used all sorts of
fancy terms I couldn’t wrap my head around. He then asked the room full of
graduate students if it made sense, and they all nodded profoundly. I didn’t
have the courage to say I was still as lost as before.
Perhaps
my own reading, proceeding only from own reflections, is still too confused or
simplistic; I am aware that I am not the sharpest tool in the shed. All I know
is that when an idea seems too abstract for me, I try to use a very concrete
analogy to nudge me along the way.
From my
love of music, I often employ the image of an orchestra or a choir to help me
think about the relationship of a whole, all of something, and a part, a piece
of something.
So we
understand that the performance of the music is like a whole, and that all the musicians
contribute to it. Yet what actually produces that harmony? We think that the
players are all somehow making the whole of the music, one by one, each through
their own different parts in the score.
But each
part, only taken in itself, is really not much at all. It is certainly not
complete. When I played the double bass, I would sometimes spend whole minutes
doing nothing at all, then suddenly produce a few quick notes, and then go back
to counting the measures until I had to do something else. When I played my
part alone at home to practice, it was certainly not a harmony; it was just
individual sounds, here and there, quite boring and tedious. It had no sense,
no rhyme or reason to it.
How
about those first violinists, or those soloists? The got to noodle their way
through the whole thing, and they were thought to be more important than the
rest of us. But they weren’t. Their fancy finger-work was still nothing in
itself, however impressive the musicianship.
No one distinct
part in the piece contains the fullness of the music, and no one musician
defines the entire work. Well then, surely they are doing it all together? Yes,
but their individual playing or singing itself isn’t doing that. Otherwise, any
playing or singing, all jumbled together, would make it a harmony.
Where is
that harmony really coming from? Not from the bottom up, but from the top down.
A composer wrote that score, and we freely follow it. A conductor assists us in
doing this, but we are still formed by that score. The musicians are not the
highest cause itself, but the means by which that cause expresses itself. They
are the matter, not the agent.
The
whole is not determined by the parts, but rather the parts are determined by
the whole. Or put another way, the many do not shape the one, and instead the
one shapes the many.
So too
it is with happiness, and so too it is with God. No one element is the
totality, and no mere combination of certain elements is the totality.
Remember
all the individual things Lady Philosophy said we thought were happiness, and
how we separated them, failing to see that they were really just mirrors of the
one and the same?
Money?
Honor? Power? Fame? Pleasure? Each of these fully reveals that perfect goal, but
absolutely none of them, isolated and only of their own accord, amount to
anything at all. Much like how the tuba player, and the timpani player, and
that sassy bassist in the back row can’t really have any meaning as separated
from the unity of the whole piece of music.
It isn’t
the sum of the parts, or the dominance of one of the parts. It is something
greater than the parts, in which all of the parts participate. Look to the
head, not to the bits of the body here and there.
Written in 9/2015
No comments:
Post a Comment