But why should I not tell you about Cato, how he read Plato's book on that last glorious night, with a sword laid at his pillow? He had provided these two requisites for his last moments—the first, that he might have the will to die, and the second, that he might have the means.
So he put his affairs in order—as well as one could put in order that which was ruined and near its end—and thought that he ought to see to it that no one should have the power to slay or the good fortune to save Cato.
Drawing the sword—which he had kept unstained from all bloodshed against the final day—he cried:
"Fortune, you have accomplished nothing by resisting all my endeavors. I have fought, till now, for my country's freedom, and not for my own, I did not strive so doggedly to be free, but only to live among the free. Now, since the affairs of mankind are beyond hope, let Cato be withdrawn to safety."
The student may be tempted to scoff and sneer at the teacher’s stories of heroes, though I have only found myself doing so when I wish to impress others by coming across as edgy and clever. Mockery tends to be a sign of insecurity, and what better remedy for feeling small than finding a better example to follow?
Whenever I begin to doubt that people are capable of such moral greatness, I remind myself how seeing the worst in others is a consequence of my own bitterness, and I reflect upon the fact that the very same power of free judgment is what permits an increase of both the virtues and the vices.
If I can choose to be a cowardly scoundrel, what is stopping me from being a valiant gentleman? Whatever my dispositions or circumstances, my thinking is the sole obstacle.
Cato the Younger is a paragon to many Stoics, and for very good reason. Our modern sensibilities may be offended by the self-inflicted violence of his passing, but none of that has much meaning without the context of his whole life, characterized by a constant struggle to champion justice. He could not bear greed and corruption, and he wasn’t shy about letting his voice be heard.
Like most men of principle, he was therefore often branded a troublemaker—despots have little patience for conviction and integrity.
I am still of the old school, one who believes that a familiarity with the classics can be a great aid in forming character, and so I would always encourage a reading of Plutarch’s Lives of the Noble Greeks and Romans. The biography of Cato the Younger has a special place for those drawn to Stoicism, and it offers a far more thorough and engaging account than any shallow textbook summary. I turn to it regularly when I feel the weight of the world.
With Julius Caesar having finally won total dominion over Rome, Cato was certain the cause of the Republic was hopeless. I do not know what I would choose in such a situation, but I do understand the reasons behind Cato’s decision: at that moment, he now possessed only himself, and the last thing he would permit is the loss of his own liberty.
Caesar might execute Cato, or send him into exile, but it was for more likely that he would be pardoned; a dictator hopes to strengthen his power through grand gestures of benevolence. Like any good Stoic, Cato prized being his own master, and he would refuse to grovel and beg, perhaps retaining his life but thereby surrendering his conscience.
We all face our own dilemmas, and yet courage always demands that if something is worth living for, it should also be worth dying for. As is so often the case, I believe Socrates said it best:
I would rather die having spoken after my manner, than speak in your manner and live. For neither in war nor yet at law ought any man to use every way of escaping death.
For often in battle there is no doubt that if a man will throw away his arms, and fall on his knees before his pursuers, he may escape death; and in other dangers there are other ways of escaping death, if a man is willing to say and do anything.
Been chewing on this one in the back of my mind for a couple days.
ReplyDeleteI lost an old friend to suicide a couple weeks ago (no one we know in common), so my take on this might be a little biased/raw.
I guess I'm having trouble seeing anything above the sin of pride in Cato's story. His death seems to be a grand version of, "I'm nobody's b*tch " I suppose the value lies in seeing the good in what motivated that pride (adherence to a set of values rather than personal comfort)?
As an aside, this reminds me of an argument a high school debate (which is competitive sophistry..fun, but don't take it seriously) coach I know told me based on the philosophy of Foucault. Namely that suicide is the ultimate act of liberty freeing oneself from the state and that, "if my opponent wants to prove her dedication to this idea of liberty, she should kill herself. If she doesn't, right here and now, I should win this round." From what I heard, a high school kid actually used that in a debate. (Not sure how I feel about a post modern and a classical stoic having apparent common ground).
Suicide is always a difficult topic, and it could take a whole book to consider the Roman custom of an "honorable death". Briefly, however, I would not assume either pride or despair on Cato's part, any more than I would do so for Socrates or Seneca. In their thinking, there will be times when surrendering one's life is a moral obligation. Think of the Thomist model of double effect, like the soldier who throws himself on the grenade. Cato and Foucault are facing in opposite directions here ;-)
DeleteFood for thought.
DeleteReminds me of a conversation I once had about martyrdom and how people find themselves under moral obligation to die for the (apparently) stupidest, smallest things.